Jump to ratings and reviews
Rate this book

An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Rate this book
La Investigación sobre el conocimiento humano constituye la exposición más coherente y madura de las ideas de David Hume (1711-1776). La obra se erige en torno a la formulación de los dos grandes principios del empirismo clásico del siglo XVII -por un lado, la afirmación de que todas nuestras representaciones se fundamentan en la experiencia y, por otro, el principio de que las cuestiones de hecho, esto es, las proposiciones fácticas, no son reductibles a las relaciones de ideas, sin que quepa establecer una dependencia jerárquica del conocimiento empírico respecto al conocimiento racional-. A partir de estos fundamentos, la exposición se centra, en definitiva, en la crítica de la noción de causa, con todas las implicaciones y derivaciones que el desarrollo de este tema central lleva consigo. Prólogo y traducción de Jaime de Salas Ortueta.

96 pages, Paperback

First published January 1, 1748

Loading interface...
Loading interface...

About the author

David Hume

2,696 books1,498 followers
David Hume was a Scottish historian, philosopher, economist, diplomat and essayist known today especially for his radical philosophical empiricism and scepticism.

In light of Hume's central role in the Scottish Enlightenment, and in the history of Western philosophy, Bryan Magee judged him as a philosopher "widely regarded as the greatest who has ever written in the English language." While Hume failed in his attempts to start a university career, he took part in various diplomatic and military missions of the time. He wrote The History of England which became a bestseller, and it became the standard history of England in its day.

His empirical approach places him with John Locke, George Berkeley, and a handful of others at the time as a British Empiricist.

Beginning with his A Treatise of Human Nature (1739), Hume strove to create a total naturalistic "science of man" that examined the psychological basis of human nature. In opposition to the rationalists who preceded him, most notably René Descartes, he concluded that desire rather than reason governed human behaviour. He also argued against the existence of innate ideas, concluding that humans have knowledge only of things they directly experience. He argued that inductive reasoning and therefore causality cannot be justified rationally. Our assumptions in favour of these result from custom and constant conjunction rather than logic. He concluded that humans have no actual conception of the self, only of a bundle of sensations associated with the self.

Hume's compatibilist theory of free will proved extremely influential on subsequent moral philosophy. He was also a sentimentalist who held that ethics are based on feelings rather than abstract moral principles, and expounded the is–ought problem.

Hume has proved extremely influential on subsequent western philosophy, especially on utilitarianism, logical positivism, William James, the philosophy of science, early analytic philosophy, cognitive philosophy, theology and other movements and thinkers. In addition, according to philosopher Jerry Fodor, Hume's Treatise is "the founding document of cognitive science". Hume engaged with contemporary intellectual luminaries such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau, James Boswell, and Adam Smith (who acknowledged Hume's influence on his economics and political philosophy). Immanuel Kant credited Hume with awakening him from "dogmatic slumbers".

Ratings & Reviews

What do you think?
Rate this book

Friends & Following

Create a free account to discover what your friends think of this book!

Community Reviews

5 stars
7,131 (34%)
4 stars
7,093 (34%)
3 stars
4,626 (22%)
2 stars
1,180 (5%)
1 star
499 (2%)
Displaying 1 - 30 of 650 reviews
Profile Image for Manny.
Author 34 books14.9k followers
November 14, 2014
I had seen so many references to Hume's Enquiry that I almost thought I had read it; but, when I actually got around to opening the book, I found as usual that things were not quite as I had imagined. I was not surprised by his relentless scepticism, or by his insistence on basing all reasoning on empirical evidence. These qualities, after all, have become proverbial. I was, however, surprised to find that I hadn't correctly grasped the essence of his argument concerning the nature of knowledge. In case you are as poorly informed as I was, let me summarise it here.

Hume's position is wonderfully simple. He asks what grounds we have for supposing that multiple repetitions of an experiment justify us in inferring a necessary law. If we note, on many occasions, that hot objects burn our hands when we touch them, what logical reason do we have for assuming that we should not touch the next candle flame we happen to see?

The answer is that we have no logical grounds at all for making such an inference. Of course, as a matter of observed fact, we do assume, after a small number of trials, that touching hot objects will hurt us. Hume says this is nothing to do with logic; we are simply designed in such a way that we cannot help being influenced by our experience to adopt such rules. As he points out, many other living creatures do the same. It is impossible to believe that a dog or a horse is performing any kind of logical deduction when they learn to avoid touching naked flames. They simply acquire the habit of behaving in this way. The most economical explanation of what we see is that human beings are doing the same thing.

A mountain of discussion has accumulated since Hume published his book, and it would be presumptuous of me to give my opinions when so many extremely clever people have already done so. I am, however, struck by something I have noticed in the course of my professional career. I have worked in Artificial Intelligence and related subjects since the early 80s, and during that period the field has suffered a profound change. In 1980, most AI research was related to logic. People assumed that the notion of intelligence was in some essential way based on the notion of deduction. Making machines intelligent was a question of making them capable of performing the right kinds of logical inferences. This tempting approach was, unfortunately, a resounding failure.

Somewhere towards the end of the last century, a different way of looking at things started to become fashionable, and quickly gained ground. Instead of thinking about logic, people began more and more to think about probability. They collected data and extracted various kinds of statistical regularities. The new AI systems made no attempt to think logically; their decisions were based on associations acquired from their experience. At first, the AI community was scornful, but it was soon found that "data-driven" systems worked quite well. They made stupid mistakes sometimes; but so did the logic-based systems, and the mechanical logicians tended to make more stupid mistakes. They could reason, but they had no common sense. Today, data-driven systems have taken over the field, and the approach has been shown to work well for many problems which had once been considered impossible challenges. Particularly striking successes have been notched up in machine translation, speech recognition, computer vision, and allied fields.

If David Hume came back today, I have no idea whether he'd be offered a chair at a philosophy department. But I'm fairly sure that Google would be interested in hiring him.
Profile Image for Ariel.
301 reviews59.8k followers
October 15, 2017
So I had to read this for my class "A Prehistory of Affect: Reading the Passions." It was a pretty panicked situation: I got randomly chosen to do a 30 minute presentation on this text... in the first week of my Masters. I had one week to read the Enquiry and prepare my presentation. It was incredibly stressful. I've never read philosophy, I'm very unfamiliar with the 18th century, and I had been out of school for year and a half. Talk about being kicked back into gear.

I don't know how to "rate" this text. It's pretty readable which was nice and a lot of the ideas are interesting and make you think.. but then a lot of the ideas are cyclical and redundant or just kind of silly. Im giving it three stars because that's what it conjures up in my mind, but I'm not super sure what I'm judging that off of, honestly. It's a text that is more about the discussion it creates rather than a "i liked it/i didn't like it" binary.

PS: The presentation went super well! I got an A! YAY!
Profile Image for Xeon.
39 reviews337 followers
December 11, 2021
Is it not uncertain whether the effect of my realizations about the disconnection of causes and effects is due to the cause of reading An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding? The most excellent definition of causation being "if the first object had not been, the second never had existed" is not true in this case since I, as with Hume, may have been able to realize this independently. It is said correlation does not entail causation, and reading Hume does not necessarily entail that it was the cause of me realizing the same ideas. It seems further experimentation will be necessary.

I submit that multiple individuals read An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding as the experimental group and have another group read randomly selected books as the control group. Then, let us have them take a reading comprehension test or perhaps have them submit reviews on some platform, call it notbadtexts.com, for comparison. Using tests of statistical significance, it will thus be able to be confirmed whether the effect of learning about the disconnection of causes and effects was indeed due to the cause of reading a book about such. I daresay this may be the most important scientific experiment on causality to ever be devised. It is imperative we test and confirm whether causal effects indeed lead to thoughts about causal effects, elsewise the entire scientific enterprise may currently be compromised.

Anyhow, the weather today was nice, and I look forward to supper.

Ah, right, but was it not also said "A wise man, therefore, proportions his belief to the evidence"? Tis true, tis true... However, an experiment of such a kind would be of the highest order of evidence. Rather than theorizing the validity of those notions, such an experiment would finally make them become a matter of fact about matters of fact. For "a weaker evidence can never destroy a stronger."

We will then be able to compound our certainty by performing an experiment on the effects of reading about an experiment (a cause) on the effects of reading about the true nature of causality from a text called An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (another cause). Ad infinitum. Thus, a means has been established of having certainty about certainty, which is the greatest form of certainty.

Has thee Bayes been beaten? Has thy necessity of Kantian transcendental pure reason been admonished?
Profile Image for امیر لطیفی.
159 reviews183 followers
August 12, 2021
دیوید هیوم همچون لاک و بارکلی از فلاسفه‌ی تجربه‌گراست. این فلاسفه معتقدند که تجربه منبع اصلی معرفت و شناخت است.

- درباره‌ی کتاب

فلسفه‌ی غامض، فلسفه‌ی واضح
هیوم فلسفه را به دو قسم تقسیم می‌کند: غامض، واضح. معتقد است که هر دو موردِ نیاز هستند. اگر فلسفه‌ی غامض به صورت تخصصی نباشد، فلسفه‌ی واضح شکل نخواهد گرفت یا شکوفا نخواهد شد. فلسفه‌ از نظر هیوم باید کاربردی باشد و در خدمت بشر. فلسفه‌ی کاربردی همان فسلفه‌ی واضح است که توسط عموم مردم قابل فهم و بکارگیری است. هیوم می‌گوید برای عموم می‌نویسد و به راستی چنین می‌کند. فلسفه‌ی مابعدالطبیعه از نظر هیوم فلسفه‌‌ای غامض و مهملی است که بیراهه می‌رود و نتیجه‌ی غلط فلسفیدن است.

منشأ ایده‌ها
به عقیده‌ی هیوم، هر فکر و ایده‌ای، چه بسیط و مرکب از تجربه می‌آید. ایده‌های مرکب، حاصل پیوستن ایده‌های بسیط هستند. در ‌نتیجه هیچ ایده‌ی فطری‌ای وجود ندارد و در حقیقت فکر و روان انسان‌ها پس از تولد همچون لوح‌های سفیدی‌ هستند که تجربه بر آنها چیزها می‌نویسد.

ارتباط ایده‌ها
ارتباط ایده‌ها به سه روش ممکن می‌شود: شباهت، مجاورت در زمان یا مکان، و علیت.

موضوع کاوش‌های بشری: حساب و هندسه، امور واقع
موضوعات کاوش‌های بشری دو نوع هستند. یکی «روابطِ بین ایده‌ها» که از جنس استدلال برهانی‌ هستند و در حساب و هندسه کاربرد دارد. در این نوع برای استدلال و نتیجه‌گیری تنها نیاز به کنش‌های ذهنی دارد. نوع دوم کاوش در «امور واقع» است. کاوش در این مورد به کمک استدلال انسانی شکل می‌گیرند و مبتنی بر علیت است. تجربه، این نوع کاوش را خوراک می‌دهد.

غریز‌ه‌ی استدلال
استدلال تجربی گونه‌ای قوه‌ای مکانیکی یا غریزی‌ست که ناخودآگاه آن را به کار می‌بریم.

علیت چیست؟
علیت از نظر هیوم قابل اثبات نیست. یعنی ما هرگز قادر به کشف رابطه‌‌ای ملموس بین علت و معمول نیستیم. بلکه تنها از تکرار اتفاقات هم‌زمان و براساس عادت و تجربه حدس می‌زنیم که رابطه‌ای وجود دارد و اسم آن را رابطه‌ی علّی می‌گذاریم. به عنوان نمونه اگر تنها یک بار سقوط شیئی را از بالا به پایین ببینیم، نمی‌توانیم چیزی را تصور کنیم یا تشخیص دهیم به نام جاذبه. ولی اگر این اتفاق تکرار شود، فکر می‌کنیم علت را یافته‌ایم و آن را با در ارتباط با جسم و زمین، «جاذبه» می‌نامیم. وقتی تنها منبع شناخت ما تجربه است، نمی‌توان مطمئن بود که رویدادهایی که تجربه کرده‌ایم، تا همیشه در مورد موقعیت‌های مشابه یکسان اتفاق خواهد افتاد.

علیت، باور، احتمالات
علیت حاصل استدلال نیست، حاصل استنتاج است. «باور» حاصل اونس و عادت به تکرار تجربه‌‌های یکسان است. وقتی از احتمالات صحبت می‌کنیم، همچنان اتکای ما به تجربه و استنتاج است.

ضرورت
اگر چیزی به نام ارتباط «ارتباط ضروری» وجود داشته باشد، چنین ارتباطی غیرقابل شناخت است. زیرا هیچ وقت با تجربه‌ی پدیده‌ها قادر به مشاهده‌ی نیرو یا انرژی‌ای نخواهیم بود که ضرورتاً اتفاقی را ممکن می‌شود یا باید بشود.

معجزه
معجزات را نمی‌توان پذیرفت [یا موجه نیست که بپذیریم] چون تنها از طریق گواهی دیگران به اطلاع ما می‌رسند. هر چقدر گواهی‌دهندگانِ رویدادها از لحاظ مکانی و زمانی از ما دورتر باشند، گواهی آن‌ها غیرقابل‌ اتکاتر است. معجزات معمولاً از فیلتر آگاهان و اندیشمندان گذر نکرده و در سرزمین مردمان نسبتاً جاهل روی داده‌اند. هیچ معجزه‌ای نیست که هم‌زمان توسط تمامِ مردمِ یک عصر، یا حتی تمام مردمانِ محل معجزه در آن عصر تایید شده باشد و مخالفی نداشته باشد. استدلال انسانی، استنتاج، و احتمالات به ما می‌گویند، هر قدر یک اتفاق نادرتر و خارق‌العاده‌تر باشد، کمتر پذیرفتنی‌ست. در امور روزمره اگر بعد از هزار بار مشاهده‌ی یک رویداد به شکلی خاص، یک بار آن اتفاق متفاوت روی دهد، به جای پذیرش یک رویداد خارق‌العاده، ابتدا به مشاهده‌ی خودمان شک می‌کنیم، یا سعی می‌کنیم بیشتر مداقه کنیم و احتمال می‌دهیم این بار شاید علتی دیگری در کار بوده است که از آن بی‌خبریم. اگر خودمان این اتفاق را متفاوت را مشاهده نکرده‌ باشیم و تنها از طرف کسی گواهی شده باشد، به گواهی‌دهنده شک می‌کنیم. در مورد معجزات هم باید چنین کنیم.

صفات خدا
اگر بتوان علت را از یک معلول شناخت یا حدس زد، نهایتاً می‌توان مشخصاتی را به علت نسبت داد که از طریق معلول قابل کشف باشد، نه فراتر از آن. ولی فیلسوفان مذهبی پا را از این فراتر می‌گذراند. نه فقط با مشاهده‌ی مخلوقات، خدا را به عنوان خالق کشف می‌کنند، بلکه صفات دیگری را هم مثل عدالت و هدفمندی را هم به آن منتسب می‌کنند. یک دلیل شاید این است که خود را جای خدا می‌گذارند. تصور می‌کنند، اگر آدمی چنین توانمند باشد که چنین چیزهایی را خلق کند، حتماً عادل است و از این کار هدفی دارد و الی آخر، پس فک�� می‌کنند که می‌توان نتیجه گرفت که خدا هم چنین است.

انواع شکاکیت
هیوم انواع شکاکیت را بررسی می‌کند. شک دکارتی را مفید می‌داند ولی معتقد است که برخلاف ادعای دکارت، این شک همه‌جانبه و واقعی نیست. نمی‌توان به همه چیز شک کرد و سپس یک نقطه‌ی آغازین و قابل اتکا را برای شروع پیدا کرد که بی‌شک از هر شکی به دور باشد و سپس به کشف امور دیگر پرداخت.

سپس شک افراطی را رد می‌کند. معتقد است که شک افراطی در بطن خود متناقض و مهمل است. اگر تلاش کنید که ثابت کنید همه چیز مشکوک است، شک خود را منکر شدید. چرا که مدعی هستید که «مشکوک بودن همه چیز» جای شک ندارد. این شک راه به جایی نمی‌برد و حتی امور روزمره هم با آن پیش نمی‌رود.

تنها چیزی که از نظر هیوم جای شک ندارد، ریاضی است. علت هم این است که در ریاضی همه‌ی واحدهای عددی با هم یکسان هستند. در نتیجه، مقایسه و نتیجه‌گیری ممکن است. ولی در امور واقع هیچ دو چیزی کاملاً یکسان نیستند و هیچ مقایسه و نتیجه‌ای نمی‌تواند دقیق و بی‌شک انجام گیرد.

امور کلی و جزئی
همه‌ی امور جزئی هستند. کلیات تنها نام‌هایی هستند برای امور جزئی که به شکلی شبیه هم هستند. همه‌ی علوم، علم به کلیات هستند.

به آتش بسپارید!
هیوم در تمام کتاب صبور است. ولی آن را طوفانی تمام می‌کند. می‌گوید هر کتابی در دست گرفتید چنین کنید: «باید بپرسیم آیا استدلالی مجرد مربوط به کمیت یا عدد را در بر دارد؟ آیا استدلالی آزمایشی مربوط به امر واقع و وجود را در بر دارد؟ نه. پس آن را به شعله‌های آتش بسپرید؛ زیرا جز سفسطه و توهم چیزی در بر نتواند داشت.»


- درباره‌ی ترجمه
مترجم در مقدمه می‌گوید که قصد دارد و بهتر است که به ساختار انگلیسی قرن هجدهمی هیوم وفادار باشد. این وفاداری به نفع خواننده تمام نشده است. در جملاتِ پرشماری، حتی ترتیب کلمات غریبه و انگلیسی هستند. به جای ساختارِ معمولِ فارسی جمله یعنی فاعل، مفعول و فعل، ساختار انگلیسی یعنی فاعل، فعل و مفعول به کار رفته است. متن بدون دلیل موجه، پیچیده و آزاردهنده شده است. حفظ ساختار اصلی متن و زیبایی نثر قدیمیِ هیوم، دلیلی‌ست که مترجم برای چنین ساختاری می‌آورد. به نظرم هدف اصلی از خواندن چنین کتابی، آگاهی نسبت به اندیشه‌ی هیوم است، نه لذت بردن از نثر آن. گرچه در نهایت نثر ترجمه‌شده، چندان لذتی را منتقل نمی‌کند.

ضمناً باز در همان مقدمه، مترجم گفته که قصد ندارد هیچ جا پاورقی بگذراد. هیچ بخشی از چیزهایی که معمولاً توقع داریم در پاورقی بیاید، نیامده است. انگلیسیِ هیچ اسمی، اطلاعات کتاب‌ها یا مکان‌هایی که در متن اشاره می‌شود، و هیچ چیز دیگری از زبان مترجم در پاورقی نیست. مترجم دلیل را سادگی متن می‌داند که آن را بی‌نیاز از شرح و توضیحات و پاورقی می‌کند. صحیح است که هیوم برای همگان و ساده می‌نویسد ولی دست‌کم در موارد فروانی، همچون انگلیسیِ نام‌ها، وجود پاورقی‌ها لازم بود و نبودشان، گرچه خوانش را ناممکن نمی‌سازد، همچنان نقص است.

خلاصه، حیف است که «کاوه لاجوردیِ» توانا، با دو انتخاب اشتباه که به راحتی قابل جلوگیری بود، کار باارزشش را دچار نقص‌هایی کرده است.

پی‌نوشت ۱:
پیشتر پلی‌لیستی از یوتیوب را پیشنهاد کرده بودم، که شامل ۸۱ جلسه‌ی تقریباً یک ساعته است از کلاس درسی درباره‌ی تاریخ فلسفه. این پلی‌لیست چنان با ارزش است که به بهانه‌ی هیوم‌خوانی دوباره می‌آورم‌اش:
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=KOO9c...
سه جلسه از این ویدئوها، مربوط به هیوم است.

پی‌نوشت ۲:
از همین کتاب شروع کردم به کمی خلاصه‌نویسی؛ خیلی خلاصه. در همان کتاب، در ابتدا یا انتهای بخش، چند خطی می‌نویسم. این مرور در حقیقت، از همان خط‌ها می‌آید. اگر نقصی داشت، خبرم کنید، چون به نیّت اینجا آمدن، نوشته نشده بوده‌اند.
Profile Image for Jon Nakapalau.
5,468 reviews820 followers
May 1, 2024
Very hard book to get through...but it may be that my 'understanding' is well below the bar Hume set...on further reflection, I am sure that that is the case - after 'empiricisticly' reflecting on my experience it is my level of understanding that made this book hard to get through.
Profile Image for J.
218 reviews113 followers
October 1, 2021
Hume is one of the best, most quotable and reasonable philosophers of all time. Besides Schopenhauer and maybe Plato, no one had a greater mind. He was not quite the lucid prosodist Arthur was, and not quite the poet Plato was, but when it comes to directing humanity away from superstition and toward rational thinking, maybe none have done as much. A friend of Rousseau's and a great historian to boot, David Hume's writings deserve our attention.
Profile Image for Peiman E iran.
1,438 reviews799 followers
February 5, 2017
‎دوستانِ گرانقدر، این کتاب یکی از سه کتابِ ارزشمندی است که از دلِ مطالبِ کتابِ اصلیِ زنده یاد <دیوید هیوم> بزرگترین فیلسوفِ تاریخ انگلستان، با عنوان "در طبیعت انسان" بیرون آمده است که اینگونه برای ریویو نویسی من نیز ساده تر و بهتر است و میتوانم در مورد نوشته های دیگر از این فیلسوفِ خردگرا، برایتان بنویسم
‎عزیزانم، هدفِ <هیوم> در این کتاب این است تا ثابت کند که ایده ها در اصل تفاوتی با تجربیات ندارند. چراکه ایده هایِ پیچیده از ایده هایِ ساده تر بیرون می آیند و ایده هایِ ساده تر نیز از احساساتِ حسی به وجود می آیند
‎زنده یاد <هیوم> میگوید: وقتی ایده و کاری را میتوان آشکار و روشن دانست که درستیِ آن از راه تجربه اثبات گردد و به وسیلهٔ غریزه نمیتوان درستی موضوعی را اثبات نمود
‎سپس این مردِ بزرگ به موضوعِ وجودِ خدا و روح میپردازد و میگوید: از آنجایی که مردم نمیتوانند وجودِ خدا را با روش آزمایش و روش های علمی و خردگرایانه اثبات کنند و اثری از روح و خدا و موهومات دینی وجود ندارد، لذا دلیلی برای اعتقاد به خدا و چیزهای دیگری که توسطِ دینکاران به مردم وعده داده شده است، وجود ندارد
‎این فیلسوفِ بزرگ، توضیحاتش را با به کاربردنِ ابزاری همچون میکروسکوپ - تیغ - چنگال.. کامل میکند و اینگونه میگوید که ما باید همچون این سه ابزارِ کاری، در زندگی به درستی و راستی پی ببریم
*******************
‎میکروسکوپ: برای فهم و درکِ یک ایده و نظرِ ارائه شده، باید آن ایده را به ایده هایِ ساده تری که اجزایِ سازندهٔ آن هستند جدا کرده و یک به یک مورد بررسی قرار دهیم
*******************
‎تیغ: باید موهومات دینی و مذهبی و همینطور مسائل متافیزیکی که دلیل علمی و خردگرایانه برای توجیه آن وجود ندارد را به وسیلهٔ تیغ از زندگی و افکارمان بزداییم و آنها را بتراشیم
*******************
‎چنگال: به وسیلهٔ چنگال میتوانیم حقایق را به دو بخش تقسیم کنیم... دستهٔ اولِ حقایق به این صورت است که برخی از ایده ها و نظرات همچون نظریاتِ درستِ ریاضی که بارها اثبات شده اند، اثباتِ آنها همیشگی خواهد بود و تردیدی در آنها وجود ندارد
‎دستهٔ دوم، راستی ها و درستی هایی هستند که از ابتدا در طبیعت و دنیا، همیشه روی داده اند و درستی آنها ثابت شده است
‎ما باید تنها به همین دو دسته از درستی ها که خردِ ما آنها را قبول کرده است و از راه دانش ثابت شده است، اعتقاد داشته باشیم
------------------------------------------------
‎امیدوارم این ریویو برای شما خردگرایان مفید بوده باشد
‎در ریویوهای دیگر سعی میکنم بیشتر به اندیشه های این فیلسوفِ بزرگ، بپردازم
‎<پیروز باشید و ایرانی>
Profile Image for Valeriu Gherghel.
Author 6 books1,714 followers
February 7, 2022
S-a întîmplat să citesc Critica rațiunii pure în anul II de Facultate, cu mult înainte de a citi Cercetare asupra intelectului omenesc. Abia atunci am înțeles afirmația lui Immanuel Kant că „a fost trezit din somnul dogmatic” de Hume. Și tot atunci am observat, cu uimire, că întrebările la care a încercat să răspundă Immanuel Kant (chiar și ordinea lor) erau, în realitate, întrebările lui David Hume formulate în Cercetare... A.J. Ayer în consideră pe Hume „cel mai important filosof britanic”. Nu mă îndoiesc că este așa, deși ierarhiile nu prea au sens. Peste tot, atitudinea lui Hume este „sceptică”. Gînditorul scoțian a văzut în scepticism atitudinea cea mai potrivită în abordarea problemelor filosofice. Totul poate fi obiect de îndoială. Consideră că răspunsurile pe care el însuși le oferă trebuie privite măcar cu un dram de scepticism.

David Hume a fost un om moderat și amabil, vestit pentru noblețea și cumpătarea lui. Dar asta nu l-a împiedicat să adopte adeseori o atitudine polemică. Discuția lui cu privire la „miracole” a rămas clasică. Mai puțini știu însă că Hume (ca și Seneca, Montaigne sau Sir Thomas Browne) nu s-a ferit să recomande un soi de „incendiu al cărților”. Există cărți inutile: „Cînd parcurgem bibliotecile, pătrunși de aceste principii, ce prăpăd ar trebui să facem? Dacă luăm în mînă orice volum de teologie sau de metafizică de școală, bunăoară, să ne întrebăm: Conține el vreun raționament abstract privitor la cantitate sau număr? Nu. Conține oare el vreun raționament întemeiat pe experiență cu privire la fapte și existență? Nu. Încredințați-l atunci focului, căci nu poate conține nimic altceva decît sofisme și iluzii” (p.225).

Aș menționa două contribuții esențiale ale filosofului englez:
1. Din „este” nu poate fi dedus niciodată „trebuie”.
2. „Post hoc ergo propter hoc” este cel mai răspîndit sofism. Dacă un eveniment succede altuia asta nu înseamnă că este efectul celui dintîi...
Profile Image for P.E..
817 reviews659 followers
July 13, 2021
Plumbing the Depths of the Human Mind


Attached Soundtrack :
Zoolook - Jean-Michel Jarre


Quotes:

'In short, all the materials of thinking are derived either from our outward or inward sentiment: the mixture and composition of these belongs alone to the mind and will. Or, to express myself in philosophical language, all our ideas or more feeble perceptions are copies of our impressions or more lively ones.'


'The contrary of every matter of fact is still possible; because it can never imply a contradiction, and is conceived by the mind with the same facility and distinctness, as if ever so conformable to reality. That the sun will not rise tomorrow is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no more contradiction than the affirmation, that it will rise. We should in vain, therefore, attempt to demonstrate its falsehood.'

'The contrary of every matter of fact is still possible; because it can never imply a contradiction, and is conceived by the mind with the same facility and distinctness, as if ever so conformable to reality. That the sun will not rise tomorrow is no less intelligible a proposition, and implies no more contradiction than the affirmation, that it will rise. We should in vain[...] attempt to demonstrate its falsehood.'

[later:]

'We have said that all arguments concerning existence are founded on the relation of cause and effect; that our knowledge of that relation is derived entirely from experience; and that all our experimental conclusions proceed upon the supposition that the future will be conformable to the past. To endeavour, therefore, the proof of this last supposition by probable arguments, or arguments regarding existence, must be evidently going in a circle, and taking that for granted, which is the very point in question.'


'What is the nature of all our reasonings concerning matter of fact? the proper answer seems to be, that they are founded on the relation of cause and effect. When again it is asked, What is the foundation of all our reasonings and conclusions concerning that relation? it may be replied in one word, Experience. But if we still carry on our sifting humour, and ask, What is the foundation of all conclusions from experience? this implies a new question, which may be of more difficult solution and explication.'


'You say that the one proposition is an inference from the other. But you must confess that the inference is not intuitive; neither is it demonstrative: Of what nature is it, then? To say it is experimental, is begging the question. For all inferences from experience suppose, as their foundation, that the future will resemble the past, and that similar powers will be conjoined with similar sensible qualities. If there be any suspicion that the course of nature may change, and that the past may be no rule for the future, all experience becomes useless, and can give rise to no inference or conclusion. It is impossible, therefore, that any arguments from experience can prove this resemblance of the past to the future; since all these arguments are founded on the supposition of that resemblance. Let the course of things be allowed hitherto ever so regular; that alone, without some new argument or inference, proves not that, for the future, it will continue so. In vain do you pretend to have learned the nature of bodies from your past experience. Their secret nature, and consequently all their effects and influence, may change, without any change in their sensible qualities. This happens sometimes, and with regard to some objects: Why may it not happen always, and with regard to all objects? What logic, what process of argument secures you against this supposition? My practice, you say, refutes my doubts. But you mistake the purport of my question. As an agent, I am quite satisfied in the point; but as a philosopher, who has some share of curiosity, I will not say scepticism, I want to learn the foundation of this inference. No reading, no enquiry has yet been able to remove my difficulty, or give me satisfaction in a matter of such importance. Can I do better than propose the difficulty to the public, even though, perhaps, I have small hopes of obtaining a solution? We shall at least, by this means, be sensible of our ignorance, if we do not augment our knowledge.'


'Thus, according to these philosophers, every thing is full of God. Not content with the principle, that nothing exists but by his will, that nothing possesses any power but by his concession: They rob nature, and all created beings, of every power, in order to render their dependence on the Deity still more sensible and immediate. They consider not that, by this theory, they diminish, instead of magnifying, the grandeur of those attributes, which they affect so much to celebrate.'


'It may be said [...] that, if voluntary actions be subjected to the same laws of necessity with the operations of matter, there is a continued chain of necessary causes, preordained and pre-determined, reaching from the original cause of all to every single volition of every human creature. No contingency anywhere in the universe; no indifference; no liberty. While we act, we are, at the same time, acted upon.'


'[...] the experimental reasoning itself, which we possess in common with beasts, and on which the whole conduct of life depends, is nothing but a species of instinct or mechanical power, that acts in us unknown to ourselves; and in its chief operations, is not directed by any such relations or comparisons of ideas, as are the proper objects of our intellectual faculties. Though the instinct be different, yet still it is an instinct, which teaches a man to avoid the fire; as much as that, which teaches a bird, with such exactness, the art of incubation, and the whole economy and order of its nursery.'


'It forms a strong presumption against all supernatural and miraculous relations, that they are observed chiefly to abound among ignorant and barbarous nations; or if a civilized people has ever given admission to any of them, that people will be found to have received them from ignorant and barbarous ancestors, who transmitted them with that inviolable sanction and authority, which always attend received opinions.'


Also see:

Utilitarianism

Freedom from the Known
Divine Invasions: A Life of Philip K. Dick

Travels in Hyperreality
Nos ancêtres les Germains : les archéologues au service du nazisme

The Crowd
Propaganda
La Langue des medias : Destruction du langage et fabrication du consentement
Profile Image for Ade Bailey.
298 reviews198 followers
June 19, 2011
Returning to an old friend! The first text I was given to study as a philosophy undergraduate, and what pleasure to revisit.

I'm not sure that Hume changed my thinking as a young man so much as brought the delight of recognition. The sweeping away of superstition, fantasy systems, spiritual mumbo jumbo and so on has never for me disabled a propensity towards reflection or deep attachment to a cleaner, less encumbered mystery. Kant, too, found his religious faith strengthened by such clarity.

I was taught philosophy very much in the empiricist and positivist traditions, and whatever crude antagonisms to these have arisen among defenders of this or that faith, have found no difficulty whatsoever in reconciling particular modes of 'philosophical' thinking with poetic, aesthetic and, yes, spiritual modes. Indeed, reading Hume is its own reward for the pleasure of the text!

There is nothing but clarity and wisdom in Hume. One has to be one's own conclusion and wisdom in considering the place of closed systems (such as language, or in this case the various Hume-given patterns) and any approach to ethics, epistemology, aesthetics, 'reality', spirit etc. (the 'noumenal') but you'd be indeed in a deep dogmatic slumber if you didn't appreciate the concision of Hume as probably the greatest help of all in beginning philosophy today.
Profile Image for Jasmine.
104 reviews205 followers
August 27, 2018
"If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: (*) For it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion." (p.120)

(*) Burning had long been a common fate of atheistic books. Perhaps Hume is suggesting here that the wrong books have been destroyed... (from the notes by Peter Millican)
Profile Image for Maica.
62 reviews202 followers
May 4, 2016
description

Addition since my first review: The Problem of Induction is always something to keep in mind, for we humans are used to finding a solid ground to maintain a sense of certainty on the events of the outside world. What reasons are we to justify that what we repeatedly experienced in the past will still continue to happen until the present or future? Where do we get that certainty? Is it reliable or is only a human need to make sense of a world that in many ways is beyond our control? And why should we make a general law out of a single or isolated event?

___

This was my first whole reading of an actual work by David Hume and it is such an experience to have read something straight from the actual philosopher instead of bits and pieces of biography or explanation of his ideas. This book was a revised form of his first work, A Treatise of Human Nature, which was not received with eagerness by the public upon its first publication.

First, my impression of Hume’s style was that he was frank to the point of being humorous at times with how he pokes at the way people think, behave and react within themselves and their environment. His choice of words and the presentation of ideas were presented in a clear and logical style. Just like any thinker, he considered himself unrestrained in going against what he thought were unreasonable beliefs, superstitions, and reinforced dogmatism, and as such, allowed himself to go deep in continuous process of questioning in matters of human thought and reaction, events, and the material world.

It is only experience, which teaches us the nature and bounds of cause and effect, and enables us to infer the existence of one object from that of another. Such is the foundation of moral reasoning, which forms the greater part of human knowledge, and is the source of all human action and behaviour.


He employed a rigorous style of empirical thinking and the way he deduced what he advocated to be the way to having correct understanding of things is through reasoning by analogy. All throughout the book, the theme of cause and effect resulting to experience, recurred in all of his ideas, and it is through this means of analogy, by applying ones understanding of experience to something newly encountered, that he applied what he thought was the correctness of knowledge in human thought and the natural world.

In this book, (though I may consider giving it a second reading), I found two striking arguments that Hume made: concerning the existence of God, and that of the material world.

In the first pages, he acknowledged the existence of a Creator by whom everything in the universe is dependent upon. But in the middle of the book, he went on to apply his method of analogy and causation to God. According to him, every effect must have a cause that brought it to existence. For example, the footprint on the sand near the sea must have been caused by a person who walked on the sand. What made us to arrive at such a conclusion was we had been taught by prior experience that such a cause (a person walking) led to an effect (footprint on the sand), and therefore, we gain an understanding of the effect simply of our previous experience of actually perceiving the cause. This was his way of rigorously applying his empirical thinking which is limited to what is ‘observed and experienced’ and then to discard everything that does not conform to this method. But then, he went on to say that the existence of God cannot be justified because even though we see the creation (which is the effect), we had no direct actual experience of its Cause (God), so how can we prove the logic of His existence?

This is where the limitation of logic and rigid empiricism is shown, though Hume will not accept it. Reason will always have its limitation, as much as Faith as how Hume subjected it with criticism will have its limitation as well. Now that in this book, Hume established how human understanding can be subjected to many factors that will deem it susceptible to many kinds of errors, so too, does his method of reasoning by experience and analogy can be subjected to similar flaws. Despite the comparison of what we know of objects and experiences applied to newly encountered objects and experiences, that does not negate the fact that each are distinct from the other with their own unique qualities. In the case of the Creator - he applies analogy, but he disregards that the Creator is distinct and His Attributes are different from His creation, and therefore for him to make an analogy in the context of the creation is unreasonable. Thus, Hume becomes a victim of logic by the fact that he failed to see the difference between what and whom he is trying to compare, because he reduced the notion of ‘qualities’ to abstract ideas existing only in the human mind.

Much criticism can be attributed to religious interpretations as practiced by so-called religious people, but the depth of faith and wisdom coming from a belief on a Creator will always make a logical sense to humanity. What Hume dealt with is narrowly confined to issues of language, but the expression of language cannot be rid of its subjectivity and sophistry on the part of human beings with the way they express and understand it, in contrast to what reality and the actual world really is.

Human understanding can indeed be flawed, but this flaw allows room for humanity to adapt to an ever-changing world. It has to grapple with continuous change, which may lead to a downward spiral of conflict and chaos or growth, since the way humans think (as influenced both by their innate nature and outside forces) lead them to act on many different ways towards their fellow beings and with the world around them. On the other hand, if empirical thinking, as what Hume employed in this book is applied in an absolutist sense and make it manifest not only in human thought but in belief, and then subject everything to the limited role of language and reasoning by analogy, including the understanding of the Creator Himself, humanity will be devoid of values and depth of wisdom. Language, thought, and experience are thus, among many, are only parts of a complex reality that humans possess, and irrespective of the perception and resulting expression of these human faculties, there is an external world that exist independent of human beings. Hume, in this book failed to make a distinction between the perceiver and the perceived. And this alludes to the second point.

The second subject was Hume’s argument on the perception of the material world. In this book, he did not go at great lengths in discussing it, although his ideas are particularly insightful in the philosophical sense:

It is universally allowed by modern enquirers, that all the sensible qualities of objects, such as hard, soft, hot, cold, white, black, etc are merely secondary, and exist not in the objects themselves, but are perceptions of the mind, without any external archetype or model, which they represent. If this be allowed, with regard to secondary qualities, it must also follow with regard to the supposed primary qualities of extension and solidity; nor can the latter be any more entitled to that denomination than the former. The idea of extension is entirely acquired from the senses of sight and feeling; and if all the qualities, perceived by the senses, be in the mind, not in the object, the same conclusion must reach the idea of extension which is wholly dependent on the sensible ideas or the ideas of secondary qualities. Nothing can save us from this conclusion, but the asserting, that the ideas of those primary qualities are attained by Abstraction, an opinion, which, if we examine it accurately, we shall find to be unintelligible, and even absurd. An extension, that is neither tangible nor visible, cannot possibly be conceived: and a tangible or visible extension, which is neither hard nor soft, black nor white, is equally beyond the reach of human conception.

Bereave matter of all its intelligible qualities, both primary and secondary, you in a manner annihilate it, and leave only a certain unknown, inexplicable something, as the cause of our perceptions; a notion so imperfect, that no sceptic will think it worthwhile to contend against it.


Hume was pointing that the material world cannot possibly exist without human perception consisting of a collection of qualities which were acquired through experience. These qualities are described to objects perceived in the material world, but at the same time, they are abstract in nature and only exist in the mind. Hume contends that the perceived world is only a collection of qualities that humans attribute to what they perceive, and the independence of the external world as existing apart from the perceiver seems to be only an illusion. This reminds me of another passage from a book entitled Consciousness by a Neuroscientist, J. Allan Hobson,

If a tree falls in the middle of a forest, does it make a sound? - George Berkeley


The immediate answer will be ‘yes’, but, ‘what sound does it make if there is nobody to hear it?’ So in this case, we have a world which is centered and continuously subjected to human perception - that in Hume’s book, is not acknowledged to be existing as independent of human, nevertheless flawed perception and understanding.

David Hume, in this book, allowed me to re-evaluate and re-confirm on a much investigative level, the ways and the limitations of human understanding. He was a frank and brutally to-the-point writer, certainly unconventional, not afraid to present alternative modes of thinking and looking at things, and he has to be commended on his empirical method which is useful in the Science disciplines.

Unfortunately, regardless of how it is presented as an objective/systematic manner, Empiricism has its own limitations like human understanding, and cannot apply in an absolutist sense on matters existing beyond the capability and scope of reason and observable experience.
This entire review has been hidden because of spoilers.
Profile Image for Mohadese.
64 reviews85 followers
October 19, 2016
تا تونستم کِشش دادم، ولی خب تموم شد متأسفانه! متن پیچیده نیست و آسان‌فهم است. به غیر از بخش اول کتاب، که فکر کنم خودِ هیوم هم خیلی دوست‌اش نداشته باشه، بقیه‌ی بخش‌ها عالی هستند. بحث معروف علیت هم در این کتاب آمده است. در بخش ده در رد معجزه بحث کرده است که خب جالب بود. خواندن‌اش رو به هرکسی که یه ذره علاقه به فلسفه داشته باشه پیشنهاد می‌کنم. مخصوصاً این‌که ترجمه‌ی خیلی خوبی هم داره. (قبلاً سعی کردم کتاب اخلاق هیوم رو به انگلیسی بخونم. و بعد از سه صفحه منصرف شدم. فهمیدن انگلیسی قرن هجدهمی خیلی سخت است.)ا
Profile Image for Olga.
245 reviews94 followers
February 3, 2023
That was not an easy read for me, especially the first part of the 'An Enquiry..' referring to the origin and association of ideas and the operations of the understanding.

'Thought can in an instant transport us into the most distant regions of the universe; or even beyond the universe, into the unbounded chaos, where nature is supposed to lie in total confusion.'
------------------------------------------------------------------------------
' All ideas, especially abstract ones, are naturally faint and obscure: the mind has but slender hold of them: they are apt to be confounded with other resembling ideas; and when we have often employed any term, though without a distinct meaning, we are apt to imagine it has a determinate idea annexed to it.'
------------------------------------------------------------------------------
'The same motives always produce the same actions; the same events follow from the same causes. Ambition, avarice, self-love, vanity, friendship, generosity, public spirit: these passions, mixed in various degrees, and distributed through society, have been, from the beginning of the world, and still are, the source of all actions and enterprises, which have ever been observed among mankind.'
------------------------------------------------------------------------------
'Men are less blamed for such actions as they perform hastily and unpremeditatedly than as such as proceed from deliberation. For what reason? but because a hasty temper, though a constant cause or principle in the mind, operates only by intervals, and infects not the whole character.'
------------------------------------------------------------------------------
'Liberty... is also essential to morality, and... no human actions, where it is wanting, are susceptible to any moral qualities, or can be the objects either of approbation or dislike. For as actions are objects of our moral sentiment, so far only as they are indications of the internal character, passions, and affections; it is impossible that they can give rise either to praise of blame, where they proceed not from these principles, but are derived altogether from external violence.'
Profile Image for Markus.
648 reviews87 followers
April 20, 2019
An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding
David Hume (1711-1776)

Hume’s philosophy on understanding is based on reasoning from experimental experience, but also from knowledge gained from tradition and customary behaviour.

He visibly draws on knowledge of a wide range of classical and contemporary thinkers, whose views are often interwoven and more easily assimilated in combination.

Hume declined any resemblance to religious school metaphysics and favoured a limited sceptic approach to science depending on circumstances.

His writings are composed in an elegantly simple style, full of common sense and would likely be accepted in modern lives understanding of natural philosophy.
Profile Image for مسعود حسینی.
Author 25 books148 followers
November 20, 2016
ترجمه شاید دقیق، ولی آزارنده ست! جملات بس که طولانی اند آدم اول جمله را فراموش می کند. تلاش شده اسلوب نگارش و سبک ادبی هیوم به فارسی منتقل شود. این، خوانش را سخت کرده. باید دست کم دو بار کتاب را به دقت خواند و بعد، از دفعه سوم به فهم استدلال های هیوم پرداخت.
فونت کتاب، صفحه بندی، و غیره خیلی عالی است. اما کاش مترجم تلاش بیشتری برای برگرداندن اسلوب نگارش هیوم به اسلوب فارسی می کرد تا مطالعه اثر آسان تر شود.
Profile Image for Rowland Pasaribu.
376 reviews79 followers
June 3, 2010
Bertrand Russell famously summarized Hume's contribution to philosophy, saying that he "developed to its logical conclusion the empiricist philosophy of Locke and Berkeley, and by making it self-consistent made it incredible." Hume is remarkable in that he does not shy away from conclusions that might seem unlikely or unreasonable. Ultimately, he concludes that we have no good reason to believe almost everything we believe about the world, but that this is not such a bad thing. Nature helps us to get by where reason lets us down.

Hume is unquestionably an empiricist philosopher, and he strives to bring the rigor of scientific methodology to bear on philosophical reasoning. His distinction between relations of ideas and matters of fact is absolutely crucial in this respect. Anything we can say about the world is a matter of fact, and thus can be justified only through experience and can be denied without contradiction. Relations of ideas can teach us about mathematical truths, but cannot, as some rationalist philosophers would have, teach us about the existence of our selves, an external world, or God.

If we are left with only matters of fact to get us by in the world, however, we find ourselves greatly limited. How can past experience teach me anything about the future? Even to infer without circularity that future experience will resemble past experience requires some principle that cannot be grounded in past experience. Without that principle, our ability to reason according to cause and effect, and thus the greater part of our ability to reason with matters of fact, is sharply curtailed.

We should be careful to note the tone Hume's skepticism takes here, however. Rather than conclude that we cannot know anything about future events or the external world, he concludes that we are not rationally justifiedin believing the things we do. Hume does not deny that we make certain inferences based on causal reasoning, and indeed insists that we would be unable to live if we didn't do so. His point is simply that we are mistaken if we think that these inferences are in any way justified by reason. That is, there are no grounds for certainty or proof of these inferences.

Hume is a naturalist because he suggests that nature, and not reason, leads us to believe the things we do. Habit has taught us that we are safe in making certain inferences and believing certain things, and so we don't normally worry about them too much. We cannot prove that there is a world external to our senses, but it seems to be a relatively safe assumption by which to live. Rather than try to justify our beliefs or identify the truth, Hume seeks simply to explain why we believe what we believe.

The Enquiry is decidedly a book about epistemology and not about metaphysics. That is, Hume is concerned about what and how we know, and not at all about what is actually the case. For instance, he does not deal with the question of whether there actually are necessary connections between events, he simply asserts that we cannot perceive them. Or perhaps more accurately, Hume argues that, because we cannot perceive necessary connections between events, the question of whether or not they actually exist is irrelevant and meaningless.

Hume is an ardent opponent of rationalist metaphysics, which seeks to answer questions such as whether or not God exists, what the nature or matter and soul is, or whether the soul is immortal. The mind, according to Hume, is not a truth-tracking device, and we misuse it if we think it can bring us to metaphysical conclusions. A Humean science of the mind can describe how the mind works and why it reaches the conclusions it does, but it cannot take us beyond the confines of our own, natural, reason.

Hume's stated method is scientific, of careful observation and inference from particular instances to general principles. The drive of scientific inquiry is to dig deeper and deeper so as to uncover a very few, very simple principles that govern all the complexities that we observe. Newton's genius gives us three very simple laws that can explain and predict all physical phenomena. Hume wishes to perform a similar feat for human understanding (the word "understanding" is used by Hume to describe most broadly the several faculties of human reason). The hope is that Hume will derive a similarly small and simple number of principles that can explain and predict the processes of human thought. His method will be to proceed from simple observation of how the mind works and how we use it in everyday life, and to infer from his observations increasingly general principles that govern our understanding until he reaches a bedrock of simplicity and clarity.

In this respect, Hume follows very much in the empiricist vein of philosophy and owes a large debt to “John Locke”. Locke moved against rationalist philosophy, best exemplified by “Descartes”, which relies heavily upon rational intuition. The empiricist tradition asserts that experience, and not reason, should serve as the basis of philosophical reasoning.

The motivation for Hume's project is made apparent in his complaint that the "accurate and abstract" metaphysics that he is pursuing is frequently looked down upon and disdained. The difficulty and counter-intuitive nature of these inquiries often lead to errors that may seem absurd and prejudicial to future generations. Even today, there is a great deal of debate as to whether there has been any real "progress" in philosophy: we may have refined our discussions and dismissed some bad ideas, but in essence we are still mulling over the same problems that concerned Plato and Aristotle. It would not be unreasonable to suggest that we are no nearer a satisfactory and final answer than the ancient Greeks. Hume hopes that scientific observation can uncover the principles that underlie our reasoning so that we can be more immediately aware of faulty logic and more easily guided along the correct path.

Ever since the scientific revolution of Newton, Galileo, and others, science has been held up as a paradigm of fruitful reasoning. In science, there is a carefully defined methodology that precisely details how we can test a theory and determine whether it is right or wrong. Though it is often difficult to determine the right answer, the scientific method usually prevents us from arriving at answers that are far from the mark. Philosophy lacks any such determinate method, and philosophers are continually taking up conflicting views. For instance, Hume's emphasis on observation goes directly against Descartes' rationalism, which disparages observation in favor of pure reason. Hume hopes that his empiricism will open the way for a carefully defined method that will not allow for such disparity amongst philosophers.

Hume also suggests that his work must be epistemically (epistemic: of, relating to, or involving knowledge; cognitive) prior to the new science that he so lauds. The scientific method is a product of careful reasoning, and is thus subject to the laws of human understanding. While science seems to be in far better shape than philosophy, it too can benefit from his work. In this way, Hume differs from his predecessor, Locke. Locke sees himself as laboring on behalf of the new science, clearing away some of the linguistic rubble that might lead to confusion. While Locke humbly sees himself as simply clearing a path for science, Hume believes that his own work must lay the groundwork upon which science can rest. If he can uncover the precise laws that govern our reasoning and inferences, this should help us draw the right conclusions in our scientific investigations.

Hume brings to bear three important distinctions. The first, and most important, is the distinction between ideas and impressions. This distinction is original to Hume and solves a number of difficulties encountered by Locke. A proper discussion of Hume's footnote would take us too far afield, but we should remark that Hume's criticism of Locke is exact and powerful. The distinction between impressions and ideas might seem quite obvious and of no great importance, but Hume is quite clever to identify the full importance of this distinction. An empirical philosophy asserts that all knowledge comes from experience. For Hume, this would suggest that all knowledge comes from impressions, and so ideas are set up as secondary to impressions.

The second distinction, between complex and simple impressions or ideas, helps draw out further the power of the first distinction. A simple impression might be seeing the color red, while a complex impression might be seeing the totality of what I see right now. A simple idea might be the memory of being angry while a complex idea might be the idea of a unicorn (composed of the idea of a horse and the idea of a horn). Complex ideas and impressions are compounded out of the simple ones.

With these first two distinctions, Hume is creating a hierarchy of mental phenomena. Since the complex is compounded out of the simple and ideas are derived from impressions, everything in our mind is based ultimately upon simple impressions. A complex idea is compounded out of several simple ideas, which are in turn derived from several corresponding simple impressions. Hume thus suggests that a term can only be meaningful if it can be connected with an idea that we can associate with some simple impressions. Hume, we should note, is silently implying that every term must be connected with some idea. In the eighteenth century the philosophy of language had not yet flourished, and it was not clear how difficult it might be to determine precisely how words, ideas, and reality link up. Hume's suggestion that all terms can be analyzed into simple impressions anticipates Russell, who argues that we can analyze all terms into simple demonstratives like "this" or "that." Hume's suggestion comprehends a picture of language according to which the words we use are a complex and opaque expression of a simpler underlying language which proper analysis can bring out.

The third distinction is the three laws of association. If the previous two distinctions give us a geography of the mind, describing its different faculties, this distinction gives us a dynamics of the mind, explaining its movement. According to Hume, any given thought is somehow related to adjacent thoughts just as any given movement in the physical world is somehow related to adjacent moving bodies. His three laws of association, then, might be seen as equivalent to Newton's three laws of motion. With them, Hume hopes to have described fully the dynamics of the mind.

There are a number of objections we might want to raise to Hume's distinctions and the way they are introduced, but we will touch on only a few briefly. First, we might ask how strictly we can distinguish between impressions. Hume argues that ideas can be vague, but that impressions are exact and that the boundaries between them are clearly defined. Is the boundary between the impression of a 57" stick and a 58" stick that clearly defined? There is some level of vagueness in our impressions that Hume does not acknowledge. We could also point out that while we are experienced in distinguishing colors, we are not so good with some other sensations. For instance, we often have trouble distinguishing between tastes.

Second, we might object to Hume's implicit philosophy of language. It seems closely linked to the idea that simple impressions are clearly defined and infallible. It is far from clear, however, why it should be desirable or possible to reduce all our language to simple impressions. What, we might ask, is the simple impression from which is derived the word "sake," for example?

Third, we might ask Hume to be clearer in his distinctions. For instance, are dream images impressions or ideas? Most likely they are ideas, since they consist of a mixture of imagination and memory. However, dreams are (arguably) phenomenally indistinguishable from waking experience: we cannot prove that we are dreaming from within a dream. Thus, all our impressions from within a dream are as real to us as we dream them as waking impressions are to us when we experience them.
Profile Image for Alp Turgut.
415 reviews129 followers
July 5, 2019
Hayatı doğru yaşamanın merkezine hisleri ve deneyimi koyarak felsefe alanında devrim yaratan "İnsanın Anlama Yetisi Üzerine Bir Soruşturma / An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding" eseriyle İskoç filozof David Hume, zihnin hislerin bir kölesi olduğunun vurgusunu yapıyor. Aldığımız kararlarda mantıktan daha çok duygularımızın esiri olduğumuzu söyleyen Hume’un belirttiği şey doğru karar verebilmemiz için duygularımızı eğitmemiz gerektiği. Kısaca, insanları ikna etmek için mantığın yeterli olmadığını, öncelikli olarak sempati, teşvik ve sanatı kullanmamız, ardından ise bunları mantıkla desteklememiz gerektiğini söylüyor. Bunu yaparken de deneyimlerimizin büyük bir rol oynadığının defalarca altını çizen ünlü filozofun asıl olayı ise din kavramının mantıklı hiçbir tarafının bulunmadığını belirtmesi. Davranışlarımızın nedeninin sorumlusu Tanrı’ysa kötü davranışlarımızın suç ortağının Tanrı olduğunu yazan Hume, böyle bir şeyin ne kadar mantıksız olduğunu ve bunun sonucunda Tanrı kavramının yanlış anlaşıldığını söylüyor. İnsanların bilgisizlikten olağanüstü gibi gördüğü olaylar sebebiyle mucize kavramının ortaya çıktığını da okuma şansı bulduğumuz kitapta Spinoza benzeri bir yaklaşım görmek mümkün. Din gibi rasyonel kavramların ihtiyaç sebebiyle alışkanlığa dönüştüğünü ima eden Hume’un asıl vermek istediği en önemli mesaj ise gözlerimizdeki perdeyi kaldıran bilginin önemi. Okudukça altını çizmekten kendinizi alamayacağınız oldukça önemli felsefi eserlerden biri olan "İnsanın Anlama Yetisi Üzerine Bir Soruşturma" finali ise çok vurucu: Nicelik ya da sayıyla alakalı soyut veya olgusal durum ve var oluş hakkında deneysel bir muhakeme içermeyen şeyleri yakın gitsin, zira içinde safsata ve yanılsamadan başka bir şey yok demektir.

İstanbul, Türkiye
07.06.2019

Alp Turgut

http://www.filmdoktoru.com/kitap-labo...
Profile Image for Drew Canole.
2,255 reviews1 follower
February 26, 2017
A few years ago I had, for lack of a better term, an existential crisis. I was completely unsatisfied with the explanations for existence/purpose that I had been given by parents/teachers/friends. It terrified me that no one had ever written about this concerns (obviously people had, I was just never introduced to them). I felt like an idiot for allowing my mind to dwell on concepts such as the basis of human understanding.

It's nice, it's calming to know that extremely intelligent people, and many of them, have been concerned with the basis of human knowledge - and a few of them were as skeptical as I was.

Hume is a beautiful person. He allows us to move past complete skepticism without the need to blindly ignore the fact that complete skepticism is a genuine concern. And he did this hundreds of years ago, under the pressures of being called an 'atheist' and other bad things that could ruin his reputation and his life. I was afraid to explore these concepts in the 21st century for fear of being called weird and depressing.
Profile Image for Ashvajit.
17 reviews2 followers
March 20, 2013
I enjoyed the straightforward, no-nonsense style of this famous philosopher. Good though he is, however, his vision of life is that of pure empiricism - that all real knowledge is gained only through sense contact. In other words he appears to completely disregard a vital aspect of the human consciousness, i.e. the possibility of gaining knowledge through contemplating the mind itself, for instance through the practice of mindfulness and meditation. Furthermore he discounts the possibility of recognizing causality, asserting that we only know that 'b' follows 'a'; we cannot know, he asserts, that 'b' is caused by 'a', or that in the presence of 'a', 'b' always arises, and in 'a's absence it does not. He thus demolishes the whole basis of modern science, together with the most basic formulation of the understanding of what it is to be a wise human being able to affirm the knowledge that flows from a healthy mind untramelled by scepticism.
Profile Image for Özgür Atmaca.
Author 2 books79 followers
October 11, 2020
Felsefe'nin dip ve farklılışan türlerine Hûme'un penceresinden bakmak biraz ağır oldu çünkü genel ve evrensel felsefe ilkelerine hâkim olmakla birlikte kavramlar ve söylemler bir süre sonra ağırlaşmaya başladı.

Özellikle Anlama yetisi üzerine, olasılık ve Hayvanların aklı hakkında olan bölümlerle her okurun bir şekilde ilişki kuracağını düşünüyorum.
Profile Image for Amin.
113 reviews3 followers
September 26, 2021
کتاب برای عموم خوانندگان نوشته شده و موضوعات به آسانی قابل فهم هستند.
برای من به عنوان گام بعد از دکارت و فلسفه شکاک، هیوم و فلسفه تجربه‌گرا انتخاب مناسبی بود.

در مورد ترجمه کتاب، باید بگم که نویسنده به سبک نگارشی هیوم وفادار مانده است. ��سخه من حدود 14 صفحه تکراری داشت که مجبور شدم آن قسمت رو انگلیسی بخونم. مترجم فارسی همه ویرگول ها، دو نقطه ها و نقطه ویرگولها و حتی ساختار جمله بندی کتاب رو بدون هیچ تغییری به فارسی برگردانده است.
تصمیم در مورد اینکه این انتخاب مناسب بوده یا نه برعهده خواننده است. برای من به شخصه و با توجه به اینکه زبان فارسی رو برای مطالب علمی و فلسفی پر از ایهام و سخت خوان می دونم، جالب نبود این انتخاب.
Profile Image for mohab samir.
402 reviews353 followers
February 23, 2022
ما هو اليقين البشرى ؟؟ إنه السراب . السراب الذى سيظل الإنسان يسعى ورائه وإن عدد أسمائه فقد يكون هو المطلق أو الحقيقة أو اللانهائى ......
لكن إذا كان هذا اليقين سرابا فماذا يفعل الإنسان ؟ هذا هو جوهر ما يرمى إليه هيوم فى هذا البحث حسب إستنتاجى وفهمى .
يبدأ هيوم مفنداً لطبيعة المعرفة البشرية وقدراتها وحدودها ثم يوضح دور التجربة ليضع لها حدودا لا لتكون هى الأساس الوحيد للمعرفة الإنسانية كما يزعم لوك وغيره من التجريبيين . ولكن لتكون على الأقل الأساس العملى لهذه المعرفة
وكذلك نجده يفند قصور الشك المطلق الديكارتى والريبية البرونية وأتباعها والتى قد تسبب جمود العقل البشرى وتوقف التطور العلمى لأنها بالتأكيد ستصيب العقل البشرى بالإحباط التام إن لم نتطرف فى هذا الإستنتاج الضرورى والذى سيلغى دور العقل من الأساس . ثم نجده مرة أخرى يحدد دور الشك وأهميته وحدود مداه .
ولهذا الحياد ولهذه العقلانية كان أكبر إعجابى بهذا البحث الذى يهتم ف الأساس بالمسألة الإبستيمولوجية .
فعلى الإنسان ان يجرب ويستنتج لكنه لا يجوز له أن يجعل من التجربه القاعدة الأساسية والأولى فى عمليته المعرفية ومن هنا يبدأ فى نقده للتجريد والصور الجوهرية فى الفلسفة القديمة والمسيحية . فإن كنا نعترف بأهمية التجربة إلا أن للعقل دور كبير فى إستنتاج القواعد العامة والتجريد ولكن ذلك التجريد لا يلزمنا ولا يبدى أى ضرورة للمناداة بوجود صور جوهرية لها وجود حقيقى بمعزل عن الواقع ومنه ينتقل إلى إحباط العقل الإنسانى فى محاولته لتصور اللانهائى أو تصور صفاته لأنه لا يجوز للعقل أن يزيد على صفات الوجود أو يطلق لها المدى إلا بقدر ما يرى من حقيقتها الواقعة وأنه لا جدوى لمحاولة تفسير غاياته أو بمعنى أدق تبريرها لأن كل الاستنتاجات تستغلق على الفهم البشرى . كذلك لا يمكن أن نتخيل له من الصفات ما لم يقع تحت تجربتنا او ما لم نكون عنه فكرة ما فى أى وقت سابق ولا ستكون لنا عنه فكرة فى وقتٍ لاحق .
ورغم ذلك فى رأى هيوم فلا يحق لأى إنسان أن ينكر وجود خالق قدير مبدع لهذا النظام وهذا الإتزان الذى يعجز العقل عن بلوغ مداه وكذلك فلا يجب على العقل ان يقف جامدا أمام دوائر المغلقة والحيرة المستمرة والشك القابل للإطلاق ولكن كذلك لا ينبغى ان نثق فى اى مسألة ثقة عمياء او ضرورية فالتجربة المستمرة التى تثبت إقتران السبب والمفعول المستمرين لا تحمل فى ذاتها أى ضرورة منطقية تستلزم إستمرار هذا الإقتران فى المستقبل فالخالق وحده هو سر وجود مثل هذه العلاقات التى يألفها الإنسان ويعتقد انها منطقية فقط لمجرد تجربته المستمرة لها .
ولقارى هذا البحث المتمعن ان يستنتج تأثر ديفيد هيوم أيما تأثير بالفلاسفة المحدثين من زم��ه وبخاصة جورج باركلى فى ريبيته التى بدلا من أن ينكرها وطد دعائمها وفيلهلم لايبنتز فى موناداته المستقلة والتى تتفاعل مع بعضها لا طبقا للقوانين الميكانيكية التى لا تملك فى ذاتها أى منطقية وإنما طبقا لإرادة خالقها المطلق القدرة .
كان بحثاً فلسفيا جيداً مثيرا للذهن وموسعاً لأفق الفكر وهو أهم ما ينتظره قارىء الفلسفة بغض النظر عن نقاط الإتفاق والإختلاف .
Profile Image for Laura Noggle.
692 reviews501 followers
September 16, 2019
“In our reasonings concerning matter of fact, there are all imaginable degrees of assurance, from the highest certainty to the lowest species of moral evidence. A wise man, therefore, proportions his belief to the evidence."

Best summary I've seen:

*As intriguing today as when it was first published, Hume's An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding is a fascinating exploration into the nature of human knowledge. Using billiard balls, candles and other colorful examples, Hume conveys the core of his empiricism—that true knowledge can only be gained through sensory experience. No other philosopher has been at the forefront of the mind than David Hume; physics, psychology, neuroscience—connections to Hume are everywhere. Here is the book that Immanuel Kant confessed to have awoken him from his "dogmatic slumber."*

In a way, it reminded me of A BriefER History of Time as Hawking also used billiard balls as explanatory props.

Especially loved the ending:

"If we take in our hand any volume of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance, let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames, for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion.”
289 reviews1 follower
February 14, 2008
Hume eviscerates the belief that we can understand anything about the world on a rational and certain basis. At his most optimistic, Hume argues that all knowledge beyond direct observation is probable rather than certain. This was an important chastenment of Enlightenment rationalism, and is generally accepted today.

But Hume's argument seems to go much farther, and the more optimistic later sections are the result of his either not recognizing the strength of his earlier arguments or deliberatly obscuring it. In the critical section, "Sceptical Doubts Concerning the Operations of the Understanding," Hume demonstrates there is no rational reason to expect future events to follow the same pattern as those in the past. To have confidence in induction, and thus science and most philosophy, is therefore a matter of faith rather than reason. There is no rational way to understand the world.

In subsequent sections, Hume presents an argument for why we believe in causation and induction. It is because, he says, observing one event invariably follow another creates in our minds the expectation that it will always be so. But, as he demonstrated earlier, there is no rational basis for this belief. Oddly, in the final sections Hume proceeds as if this belief is justified, and offers critiques of miraculous and natural religion.
Profile Image for Amy.
2,750 reviews539 followers
April 15, 2020
"After all, I may, perhaps, agree to your general conclusion in favour of liberty, though upon different premises from those, on which you endeavour to found it. I think, that the state ought to tolerate every principle of philosophy; nor is there an instance, that any government has suffered in its political interests by such indulgence. There is no enthusiasm among philosophers; their doctrines are not very alluring to the people; and no restraint can be put upon their reasonings, but what must be of dangerous consequence to the sciences, and even to the state, by paving the way for persecution and oppression in points, where the generality of mankind are more deeply interested and concerned."

Though perhaps not the central takeaway to this work, the above quote struck me, especially in light of the twentieth century.
Though short in pages, An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding packs a punch with philosophy. I struggled a bit to understand it, but I could also easily see how he wrote for "popular" audiences. Not my favorite by any means, but thought-provoking.
Profile Image for Andrew.
2,091 reviews792 followers
Read
June 9, 2011
What I like about Hume is the skepticism and empiricism. What I don't like about Hume is the doubting of causality. Too bad this is pretty much thought of as the Hume thing.

Hume was a very, very necessary step in the evolution of philosophy. He overcame the irrational rationalism of Descartes and Berkeley, and paved the way for German idealism, which of course led to Schopenhauer, Marx, Nietzsche, etc. And really, I find Hume's brand of Enlightenment thought so much more palatable than Kant's or Hegel's.

And, other than the causality thing, it's really a very well-reasoned epistemology by my book-- most human knowledge among most humans is ultimately derived from habit and impulse rather than rational decision-making and inquiry. i can only imagine how refreshing this must have been when it was first published.
Profile Image for sologdin.
1,751 reviews696 followers
April 1, 2016
every time i read hume, i feel a little nauseated. my nausea is accordingly constantly conjoined to my reading of hume. am i reasonable or not in assuming a necessary connection therewith? is it irrational to assume that nausea will always follow the reading in the future just because it always has done so in the past? even if in the past the future has always been like the past, and so i can assume that in the future the past will have always been like the future, indeed, constantly conjoined with same?
Profile Image for Xander.
440 reviews158 followers
October 17, 2019
An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding (1748) was David Hume's second attempt to offer readers his view on epistemology. A Treatise of Human Nature (1739) was no succes and Hume even suffered from a depression following this failure. Nevertheless, he was convinced of the importance of the message, so he decided to publish its contents in two new, thinner and more accessible books.

In order to understand Hume's message, we have to understand the historical context of the book. In the 17th century mechanical science took over the scepter from christian scholastic philosophy. For centuries, scholars had tried to grasp reality by building axiomatic-deductive systems of knowledge, according to the philosophy of Aristotle. In other words, philosophers could understand the world from their armchairs.

Galileo demolished this worldview, and for this he was thanked by the Church of Rome with an appropriate sentence of life long house arrest. What Galileo did, was to observe the behaviour of Nature in carefully controlled experiments. From then on it was clear that Aristotle's philosophy was falsified on all accounts: the discovery of the vacuum; the observations of comets and supernovae and of planetary satellites - both happening in supposedly unalterable heavenly spheres; Aristotle's assumption that heavier objects fall faster; etc.

In 1687 Newton published his Principia and with this synthesized all the discoveries in physics and astronomy of the past 100 years in one universal system, comprising 'just' 4 laws (three laws of motion and universal law of gravity). With Newton, the Western worldview changed drastically: the only role for God was a master watchmaker, who created this universe and set it running. But more importantly, for philosophy at least, was the change of our conception of truth. Newton induced a grand system from particular observations; and induction was never before used as a scientific method.

Thinkers like John Locke (in his Essay Concerning Human Understanding) and Berkeley (in his Principles of Human Knowledge) would ponder the question of what knowledge is. How do we know what's true knowledge? According to Locke, there is an objective reality out there, but our intellect is too limited to grasp it - the best we can hope for are scientifically informed opinions. Someone like Berkeley even went so far to say that there's no such thing as objective reality: all our sensations and reflections are mental constructs, ultimately build by God.

A second key element in understanding Hume, is the discovery in the 18th century of the works of Sextus Empiricus - an ancient Greek sceptic philosopher, who found a contradiction in the method of induction. When we induce, we derive universal statements from particular observations. But there's no way to garantuee that the next observation will NOT contradict our current (universal) conclusion. So either we have to make all the observations - past, present and future - which is impossible, or we have to admit that induction is not true knowledge.

It is in this historical situation (the 17th century developments in physics and the re-discovery of the works of Sextus Empiricus) that we have to situate David Hume. Now, what does Hume say about the question of what true knowledge is?

Hume begins by explaining what causation is. According to Hume, causation is nothing but custom. When one billiard ball bounces against another, we only notice the movement of the first ball, the temporary bond between both balls and consequently the movement of the second ball. In other words: we see events following each other, nothing more or less. Now, human beings observe from the time they're born onwards certain events following each other. Ever since I can remember, I have seen objects fall to the ground when let loose. This forms in my understanding the custom of "object let loose, followed by fall". This is - according to Hume - causation.

Next, Hume has to explain what learning is. For him, learning is observing experiences and generalizing from these experiences to expectations about the future. In other words: learning is induction. We induce general conclusions (and predictions and expectations) from all the experiences we have observed. But this brings us to the 'induction problem' of Sextus Empiricus: by definition induction is unreliable as a foundation for true knowledge, since we can never with certainty form infinite conclusions from the finite data available to us.

But there is an important distinction here (known as Hume's fork), which is based on Hume's explanation of our ideas. According to Hume, we perceive (simple) ideas via our senses and then connect these ideas into associations (i.e. complex ideas) via reflection. The relationship between ideas can be known by reason alone, a priori. The ideas themselves cannot be known by reasoning a priori, only after they have been generated via our sensual perceptions - a posteriori. In other words: mathematical and logical ideas - ideas about relationships between concepts - can be known a priori, while scientific ideas can be known only by observation.

Since a priori reasoning cannot inform us on certain knowledge about the reality - this requires sensual perceptions - we cannot attain true knowledge about the world. Like Locke, Hume asserts that science can approach this ideal, but we as human beings are limited by our intellectual capabilities. In other words: reasong powers are gradual and there's only a difference of degree between us and animals. This point is extremely important, since - unlike today where this is a generally accepted statement - in Hume's time human beings were seen as the epitome of Nature's Great Chain of Being.

So by closing this book and being convinced by Hume - as we all should be - we have become sceptics: induction is our only means of acquiring factual knowledge about the world, but this method is philosophyically flawed. Now what?

Well, causation and determination have become problematic ever since the discovery of quantum mechanics - in which uncertainty and indeterminacy are principles (!) - but this doesn't bring us any further, since an indeterministic, uncertain world is - by definition - not knowable. The search goes on...

But, with Hume, we should at least by happy that we have given ourselves criteria by which to judge the truth claims of others. So even though we have given up the aim of attaining certain knowledge about the world, we have acquired a resistance to the truth claims of others. As Hume so humorously writes, every book of someone claiming to illustrate how the world works: "Commit it then to the flames: For it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion."

(It is easy to see that such a sceptical mindset is toxic to religious convictions - it leads to religious critique by definition - and it is therefore not hard to grasp why Hume's life was one of strife with religious people, why he was called an atheist, and why he had to publish some works posthumously).
Profile Image for Kamyar.
38 reviews3 followers
January 29, 2022
Did a little research on Deleuze’s famously unconventional reading of Hume, and found this.

“On Deleuze’s account, Hume is above all a philosopher of subjectivity. His central concern is to establish the basis upon which the subject is formed.

Deleuze insists that one of Hume’s greatest contributions to modern philosophy is his insistence that all relations are external to their terms: this is the essence of Hume’s anti-transcendental stance. Human nature cannot unite itself, there is no ‘I’ which stands before experience, but only moments of experience themselves, unattached and meaningless without any necessary relation to each other. A flash of red, a movement, a gust of wind, these elements must be externally related to each other to create the sensation of a tree in autumn.

In the social world, this externality attests to the always-already interested nature of life: no relation is necessary, or governed by neutral laws, so every relation has a localised and passional motive. The ways in which habits are formed attests to the desires at the heart of our social milieu.

Subjectivity, as Deleuze describes it through his reading of Hume, is a practical, passional, empiricist concept, immediately located at the heart of the conventional, which is to say the social.”
Displaying 1 - 30 of 650 reviews

Can't find what you're looking for?

Get help and learn more about the design.