Jump to ratings and reviews
Rate this book

The Principles of Psychology: Volume 1

Rate this book
This is the first inexpensive edition of the complete Long Course in Principles of Psychology, one of the great classics of modern Western literature and science and the source of the ripest thoughts of America’s most important philosopher. As such, it should not be confused with the many abridgements that omit key sections.
The book presents lucid descriptions of human mental activity, with detailed considerations of the stream of thought, consciousness, time perception, memory, imagination, emotions, reason, abnormal phenomena, and similar topics. In its course it takes into account the work of Berkeley, Binet, Bradley, Darwin, Descartes, Fechner, Galton, Green, Helmholtz, Herbart, Hume, Janet, Kant, Lange, Lotze, Locke, Mill, Royce, Schopenhauer, Spinoza, Wundt, and scores of others. It examines contrasting interpretations of mental phenomena, treating introspective analysis, philosophical interpretations, and experimental research.
It remains unsurpassed today as a brilliantly written survey of William James’ timeless view of psychology.

720 pages, Paperback

First published January 1, 1890

Loading interface...
Loading interface...

About the author

William James

352 books1,218 followers
Librarian Note: There is more than one author in the Goodreads database with this name.

William James (January 11, 1842 – August 26, 1910) was an American philosopher and psychologist who was also trained as a physician. The first educator to offer a psychology course in the United States, James was one of the leading thinkers of the late nineteenth century and is believed by many to be one of the most influential philosophers the United States has ever produced, while others have labelled him the "Father of American psychology". Along with Charles Sanders Peirce and John Dewey, he is considered to be one of the greatest figures associated with the philosophical school known as pragmatism, and is also cited as one of the founders of the functional psychology. He also developed the philosophical perspective known as radical empiricism. James' work has influenced intellectuals such as Émile Durkheim, W. E. B. Du Bois, Edmund Husserl, Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, Hilary Putnam, and Richard Rorty.

Born into a wealthy family, James was the son of the Swedenborgian theologian Henry James Sr and the brother of both the prominent novelist Henry James, and the diarist Alice James. James wrote widely on many topics, including epistemology, education, metaphysics, psychology, religion, and mysticism. Among his most influential books are Principles of Psychology, which was a groundbreaking text in the field of psychology, Essays in Radical Empiricism, an important text in philosophy, and The Varieties of Religious Experience, which investigated different forms of religious experience.
William James was born at the Astor House in New York City. He was the son of Henry James Sr., a noted and independently wealthy Swedenborgian theologian well acquainted with the literary and intellectual elites of his day. The intellectual brilliance of the James family milieu and the remarkable epistolary talents of several of its members have made them a subject of continuing interest to historians, biographers, and critics.

James interacted with a wide array of writers and scholars throughout his life, including his godfather Ralph Waldo Emerson, his godson William James Sidis, as well as Charles Sanders Peirce, Bertrand Russell, Josiah Royce, Ernst Mach, John Dewey, Macedonio Fernández, Walter Lippmann, Mark Twain, Horatio Alger, Jr., Henri Bergson and Sigmund Freud.

William James received an eclectic trans-Atlantic education, developing fluency in both German and French. Education in the James household encouraged cosmopolitanism. The family made two trips to Europe while William James was still a child, setting a pattern that resulted in thirteen more European journeys during his life. His early artistic bent led to an apprenticeship in the studio of William Morris Hunt in Newport, Rhode Island, but he switched in 1861 to scientific studies at the Lawrence Scientific School of Harvard University.

In his early adulthood, James suffered from a variety of physical ailments, including those of the eyes, back, stomach, and skin. He was also tone deaf. He was subject to a variety of psychological symptoms which were diagnosed at the time as neurasthenia, and which included periods of depression during which he contemplated suicide for months on end. Two younger brothers, Garth Wilkinson (Wilky) and Robertson (Bob), fought in the Civil War. The other three siblings (William, Henry, and Alice James) all suffered from periods of invalidism.

He took up medical studies at Harvard Medical School in 1864. He took a break in the spring of 1865 to join naturalist Louis Agassiz on a scientific expedition up the Amazon River, but aborted his trip after eight months, as he suffered bouts of severe seasickness and mild smallpox. His studies were interrupted once again due to illness in April 1867. He traveled to Germany in search of a cure and remained there until November 1868; at that time he was 26 years old. During this period, he

Ratings & Reviews

What do you think?
Rate this book

Friends & Following

Create a free account to discover what your friends think of this book!

Community Reviews

5 stars
330 (45%)
4 stars
240 (33%)
3 stars
121 (16%)
2 stars
24 (3%)
1 star
10 (1%)
Displaying 1 - 29 of 29 reviews
Profile Image for Chrissy.
442 reviews94 followers
November 22, 2011
This was an extremely fascinating, challenging, and at times infuriating read: Fascinating because James accurately predicted so much of modern psychology in 1890, before the experimental method really existed (beyond psychophysics, which he lambasts as a waste of time when one could just introspect instead); Challenging because he roots so many of his insights and explanations in classical philosophy, a slow and thorough approach that breaks the issues down to their fundamental assumptions for examination (I'm not at all used to approaching psychology in this way, and it was extremely rewarding, if laborious); Infuriating because for all he got right, he also got so, so much wrong. James was a religious man, and while he tries to leave spirituality separate from the study of psychology, it regularly seeps back in through his language and assumptions throughout. Case in point: Mind Dust from the Soul.

The book is also home to a wide gamut of hilariously antiquated social faux-pas, from racism to sexism to good old classism. The "old Princeton boys" manner of speech is pure comedy when applied to an elaborate discussion of how boring Germany must be for psychophysics to have come into existence. I got a lot of enjoyment from the book for this rich-white-Victorian comedy appeal alone.

I'm actually really, really glad I read this book. It doesn't offer much in the way of real insight into my own work, but I feel my perspective has broadened significantly through a consideration of my field's humble roots.
Profile Image for Amy.
577 reviews39 followers
January 10, 2020
Wow. He didn’t cut any corners in his explanations and arguments. This tomb is incredibly detailed and surprisingly really witty throughout thanks to that Victorian stiff upper lip bourgeois style of thinking. You can tell he absolutely loves his field, and work and is vibing on thinking through every single principle of psychology that he can come up. James is so incredibly well read and seems to know everyone in this field at the time. He is certainly no dummy. As someone who enjoys learning about different subjects and who never studied any psychology per se, (he also goes deep in metaphysics which Im fairly familiar with) I learnt a tremendous amount from this at times grindingly long book. Overall I’m very glad I stuck with it, and I have no doubt a bunch of the science parts are out of date but regardless, it was a thorough and fascinating read that I would recommend to anyone wanting a very comprehensive overview of everything psychology.
Profile Image for Jamey.
Author 8 books83 followers
October 31, 2007
Written in 1890, it's a classic tastycake! In chapter 10, "The Stream of Thought," James lays the groundwork for Joyce and Woolf and all that good stuff.
14 reviews1 follower
April 5, 2013
This extraordinary book published in 1890 describes psychology in terms that would be just as applicable today as they were in his day. William James did an amazing job of presenting this complex subject in logical step-by-step terms that support his opinions both biologically and psychologically. Highly recommended for those interested in the subject.
Profile Image for Matt.
458 reviews
March 9, 2019
A fantastic blend of philosophy, psychology and 19th century neurobiology. It is, unavoidably, dated as all science books seem to be chained to the limits of progress of the time. But the discussion of mind and philosophy retain a timelessness given the continued mystery they pose.

James’ writing reveals his classical roots. His discussions flow between epistemology and physiology. One moment he is discussing the impact of Aristotle, the next he is comparing it to our understanding of brain hemispheres. He dips and dives into why and how we perceive the world around us using every tool available to him.

But knowing that our scientific understanding has progressed far beyond James’ understanding in his day, one can’t help but wonder what his writing provides the modern reader. For those seeking a book on the facts and mechanics of the brain, this is foundational at best. However, if you read it as a philosophical work, I think the modern reader can find great pleasure in it. His scientific desire to understand trims the excess found in more “pure” philosophical works. His pragmatic analysis carves out a place for him in the Western canon. His psychology critiques stoicism and challenges Platonic tradition:
Why, from Plato and Aristotle downwards, philosophers should have vied with each other in scorn of the knowledge of the particular, and in adoration of that of the general, is hard to understand, seeing that the more adorable knowledge ought to be that of more adorable things, and the things of worth are all concretes and singulars. The only value of universal characters is that they help us, by reasoning, to know new truths about individual things… In sum, therefore, the traditional universal-worship can only be called a bit of perverse sentimentalism, a philosophic “idol of the cave.”Pp. 479-480.
Where James is probably most profound is in his examination of consciousness and the process of thought. Not only are we limited by our senses, but we are limited by what we have attuned our senses process. We perceive not only what we see, but what we have been trained to pre-perceive. The resulting stream of consciousness ebbs and flows with insight and understanding. Thought is not a defined package of ideas. It is murky and rages between the banks. However, it is by capturing moments from it, that we can define and discuss them:
Thought is in fact a kind of Algebra, as Berkeley long ago said, “in which, though a particular quantity be marked by each letter, yet to proceed right, it is not requisite that in every step each letter suggest to your thoughts that particular quantity it was appointed to stand for.” Mr. Lewes has developed this algebra-analogy so well that I must quote his words: “The leading characteristic of algebra is that of operation on relations. This also is the leading characteristic of Thought. Algebra cannot exist without values, nor Thought without Feelings” […] It need only be added that as the Algebrist, though the sequence of his terms is fixed by their relations rather than by their several values, must give a real value to the final one he reaches; so the thinker in words must let his concluding word or phrase be translated into its full sensible-image-value, under penalty of the thought being left unrealized and pale. Pp. 270-271.
Where Plato saw the key to knowledge in geometry and forms, James finds it in algebra and motion. It’s a beautiful dichotomy.
477 reviews27 followers
September 29, 2019
Up and down read in terms of what it offers, but made consistently entertaining by James tendency to emit brilliance when you least expect it. His writing style is so fun, and he does a wonderful job of characterizing and elucidating various psychological phenomena. This book can be read through so many lenses. For starters, it is a great way of thinking about the limits of the psychological sciences. How far have we come since James? I found myself constantly frustrated that I couldn't check his claims/findings against 'current consensus,' but in many places where I did have greater knowledge of the material I was struck by how much James synthesis matched findings that have been dressed up as "new" in the time since. The book is also a great example of historical psychology, and well of fun/odd facts. While there is so much overlap between James' understanding of the mind and our present one, the points of departure are fascinating in their own right as examples of how mental conceptions can evolve. On more philosophical topics like the self, consciousness, the status of concepts, and others, James is at his best. Particularly the section on the self stood out as an anticipation of much what I found profound in Parfit, and while I certainly think there is room to contest James in some areas, he looks awfully prescient in many respects. I'm not sure if I'll dive into part 2 all that soon because the book did get somewhat tiring as it went through more minutia of 19th century experiments I don't have the present day context to evaluate, but this definitely stimulated my interest for more William James. What a totality of man is he.
Profile Image for Erin Blaire.
27 reviews1 follower
February 6, 2021
In his work The Stream of Thought, James tackles the fundamental notions of how we come to understand the matters of our own consciousness (which he defines as the multiplicity of objects and relations). For James, consciousness can only be one's own (that no two consciousness can ever be exactly identical), and consciousness "goes on."
James is discontent with psychologists who deem consciousness through an unfounded verisimilitude with sensations. Sensations, according to James, cannot stand by themselves, for they are necessary results of discriminative attention.

James then sets the rest of his work clarifying what he means by consciousness (that are unlike sensations that are mere results of discriminations) "goes on" in the human mind.

First, James defines thought as a "personal form" to indicate the peculiar quality of each person's consciousness. Thoughts, for James, "belong" together, but belong together in one's own mind. No one's 'thoughts' are separate from one another, for one's own thoughts necessarily belong to one's other thoughts. The only states of consciousness for James, are located in the "personal consciousness" of one's own minds, selves, the "concrete, particular I's and you's" in which no one can have direct sight of thought into another person's consciousness.
James describes that this phenomenon is "absolute insulation and irreducible pluralism."

Secondly, James contends that the thought constantly changes for "that which takes place in sensible intervals of time" can never be "identical with what it was before."
He presents his argument for this claim by postulating that whether we think or do not think, we always have a succession of different feelings. He moreover explains that when we actually pay close attention to the matter, we will come to realize that we do not experience the same bodily sensation twice in perceiving an object.
What stays the same may be the "object" such as hearing the same note over and over again or seeing the same quality of green as the grass. However, we do not realize that we experience these objects differently when we do not attend to sensations as "subjective facts" and instead use them merely as stepping stones to pass over to the recognition of the realities (the object).
We are prone to not attend to the different ways in which the same things look/sound/smell at different distances under different circumstances, for we are inclined to ascertain the "sameness of things."
But James beckons us to recall the ways in which the same object may appear differently to us as we are sleepy or awake, hungry or full, fresh or tired, or as we go through different stages in life from childhood to adulthood. Our feelings towards the same object changes as we pass from one age to another or when we are in "different organic moods."
James goes on to say that this indicates that every sensation does in fact correspond to some cerebral action, and there is no such thing as an "identical sensation" for it would require an unmodified brain and unmodified feeling which is a physiological impossibility.
In other words, our state of mind is never precisely the same, and our thoughts, feelings, and the overall experience of an object differ in each circumstance, though we may be inattentive to the changes.
James builds up a case for his phenomenology:
The subjective experiences of the same object differently, and experience remolds us every moment, and our mental reaction on every given thing is a resultant of our experience of the whole world up to that date.
Every brain-state is partly determined by the nature of this entire past succession. Each present-brain state is a record, in which the Omniscient eye will read all the foregone history of its owner. Each present is altered by the past success and the organ has been left at that moment by all it has gone through in the past. Therefore, no two ideas can be exactly the same for each idea belongs to a specific place in time.
To even believe in the possibility of a permanently existing "idea" is to only be concerned with the "facts" the mental states reveal, rather than the complexities of the mental states themselves.

Thirdly, James points to the fact that within each personal consciousness, thought is continuous (that is, without break, crack, or division).
What we may consider "breaches" in a single mind are mere interruptions or time-gaps, which are breaks in the quality or the content of the thought that may seem abrupt.
However, James nonetheless clarifies that the thoughts within each personal consciousness are continuous, for even when there is a time-gap, the consciousness after feels as if it belonged together with the consciousness before, as another "part" of the "same self."
James also repudiates any type of "absolute" sense of abruptness in one's consciousness for there will be even a dim sense of continuity, the sense that parts are connected and belong together as part of a "common whole" which is the self whom all these thoughts belong to.
This phenomenon James calls, the community of the self, for one feels the warmth, intimacy, and immediacy of one's present thought that surely belongs to oneself. These qualities of warmth and intimacy to the self will also be connected to future considerations of thought, and past feelings also come with these qualities as the past also receives the greeting of the present mental state. The past, present, future all belong to a community of the self. Jameisan self is connected by psychological connectedness between the past, present, and future self as a coherent whole that fundamentally differs from Derek Parfit's successive selves. For example, Parfit denies that there can ever be a coherent self for there is no such thing as a "permanent self." What exists in the present brain state can only be classified as the present "self" and the next brain state is a distinct self. The chain of successive selves (notice, he uses the metaphor chain unlike Jamesian metaphor of the stream that flows together) are linked together through "memory," yet each self is distinct from previous and future self. There is no "person" that all these selves share, for a collective "I" is merely an illusion.
Rather than Jamesian psychological connectedness of selves via continuity in thought, Parfit denies that there can be continuity and connectedness enclosed within one single life. Instead, his notion of successive selves are made possible by the degree of psychological connectedness to others. What Parfit is suggesting here is a much more tenuous "I" than the atomistic sense of individuality. Rather than a Jamesian community of "self" Parfit proposes a "community of selves' that are necessary for these successive selves to have any sort of meaning.

On the whole, I can understand why Jamesian notion of the self as continuous and coherent can receive criticisms from many philosophers whose notion of the self is necessarily contingent upon the contexts and communities that will allow for the formation of selfhood. Is selfhood a given? Is consciousness that is continuous made possible by efforts of the will? For what can be said about situations of trauma in which there is such an absolute sense of abruptness in which the qualities of "warmth and intimacy" of thought to the self is no longer possible? For the thoughts that the self once had no longer has any vestiges of a connection to the present self? To this, I may agree with Parfit in that successive selves seem to fit better than a coherent, continuous self. Though, I also do not believe all individuals would necessarily go through life in the way Parfit describes it. One's experience of life, depending on the severity of trauma and trauma's impact on the psyche, can be a mixture of continuous and successive selves.
49 reviews
January 23, 2023
This is one massive book with an incredible amount of scientific discovery. Psychology at the end of the 19th century was all about studying and describing how the brain actually works from the way neurons act in the physical organ to how memory works, etc. This book is going to need a few re-reads from me down the line to understand it all, if I even bother. It's so detailed. If you find yourself interested in the actual science of how the brain works then this book is for you. Otherwise, it's a tough slog. Definitely not for those interested in the more Jungian aspects of psychology or how various personalities form or deviancy. This book doesn't get much into any of that.
March 19, 2013
Amazing insights and extraordinary neurological detail along with extremely cogent reasoning gives this book a modern aura if it weren't for the antiquated language. A startling look into a brilliant 19th century mind.
Profile Image for Sean Murray.
102 reviews1 follower
March 31, 2018
A hard slog.
Read it if you must. It’s a sensible “deep background” book for most of psychology. Naturally, it’s pretty badly outdated in places. An important historical document
Profile Image for Melsene G.
784 reviews3 followers
November 11, 2019
Unless you're a psychology major or this is required reading, you will not get much out of this huge volume. It was originally published in 1890 or so and it's dense, hard to understand, and verbose. I followed the author's instructions and skipped the designated chapters per the preface. I look at this book as a foundational overview of this science. After all, the author is the guru and father of psychology and is quoted in every psychology/science/neurology book ever written. That said, it's still an extremely tough read. Plus, in the last 100 years, what we know about science, the brain, etc., has changed astronomically with technology, and so much of what's in this book is not current. If Mr. James was alive today, he'd have a lot more to say!

I do have Volume 2 waiting in my queue and will get to it at some point, not soon though.
Profile Image for Enpitsu.
5 reviews1 follower
March 4, 2020
In a most surprising way I stumbled upon William James as a writer and his works. As someone who has a big interest in psychology, I decided to order this volume and the next using a gift card I received. His works blew a dent in my resolution to read 50 books this year, but with good reason.

William James is an incredibly thorough and structured writer. The first nth of chapters lays fundamental groundwork, think of neurology, before approaching topics that goes in depth. It takes a lot of time and attention to digest the chapters properly, otherwise you might miss the point a page later. There's also input drawn from philosophy, which is an interesting take, but William James does make it work.

I have too little a background to actually criticize his ideas here, especially since it's safe to assume that a portion of it is outdated, considering this book is over a 100 years old. But judging from other reviews and that his works are still being referenced to this day, does make me feel like this serves a good groundwork or fundament where one can branch out to modern subjects in psychology. Of course, only time will tell for me if that statement actually is true.
Profile Image for Keegan Landrigan.
12 reviews17 followers
May 30, 2021
One of the most bizarre reads in the entire history of science. So many chapters deserve 5 stars unto themselves, that it is difficult not to grant 5 stars to the whole, but the turns this book takes from neuro-anatomy to mystic panpsychism makes the whole feel at times oddly less than the sum of its parts. It helps, when reading it through this lens, to have on hand a fairly-mainstream history of experimental psychology like Edwin Boring's _History of Experimental Psychology_, to understand how lab psychologists managed to take away the things they apparently did from it.

The whole earns its way back to five stars despite these qualms by being suffused with the literary sensibility of the James family.
Profile Image for Ogi Ogas.
Author 10 books106 followers
September 15, 2023
My ratings of books on Goodreads are solely a crude ranking of their utility to me, and not an evaluation of literary merit, entertainment value, social importance, humor, insightfulness, scientific accuracy, creative vigor, suspensefulness of plot, depth of characters, vitality of theme, excitement of climax, satisfaction of ending, or any other combination of dimensions of value which we are expected to boil down through some fabulous alchemy into a single digit.
7 reviews
December 1, 2020
William James,describes his present time understanding of psychology furthermore this book was very intriguing and exciting William somehow described the modern day understanding of psychology and what has been accepted to be true to many scientist.William describes as the book title says the principles of psychology.This was a great book for better understanding the roots of psychology and how it began.
July 5, 2023
Di questo libro ho letto solamente la parte riguardante le leggi delle abitudini e sono rimasta impressionata dalle grandi anticipazioni che James riesce a presentare riguardo al funzionamento della mente. Un libro scorrevole e ben scritto, un classico da leggere se si studia o si è interessati alla psicologia
29 reviews
October 31, 2023
The intro or foreword did warn us to probably not read from start to finish. There were some amazing parts though - I took almost all of my notes from pages 250-450, so I'd strongly recommend reading that. The rest isn't particularly relevant over 100 years later.
1 review
Read
August 17, 2021
i think i will be good on psycholgy.
This entire review has been hidden because of spoilers.
Profile Image for Bob Nichols.
940 reviews326 followers
March 12, 2011
In this abbreviated (1893) edition of his classic work, James' model for how we interact with the environment is simple enough. Input comes from environmental stimuli, the brain processes it and converts it into bodily output (action). "The whole neural organism," he writes,"...is, physiologically considered, but a machine for converting stimuli into reactions; and the intellectual part of our life is knit up with but the middle or 'central' part of the machine's operations."

James has one-half of the interaction right. We do react to stimuli, but his model has us as passive responders to what comes at us from the outside. We are more than what this model suggests. Drawing from Schopenhauer and from Darwin, we are impelled to go out into the world by Will (Schopenhauer) to actively seek (food, shelter, sex, status, love, group membership, etc.) what we need for survival and well being. The fuller model is, sequentially, life energy (Will, biological survival), species-specific life energy, and individual propensities (inborn character)all are involved in directing how we react to what comes at us, how we seek the objects (objectives) we need, and how much energy that is applied to them. Viewed this way, reaction and seeking are active components in the service of survival. Importantly, our interaction with the environment starts from within.

James' model may reflect a residual inheritance of the Western philosophical tradition coming from Plato and others that believes the mind rides supreme. James may also advance as well as reflect a behaviorist model where human nature slides into the background, which leaves human reason free to create ideals for humans and society.

When James refers to will, he means rational control, not the core, inner impulse that is Schopenhauer's Will that pushes reason. When James refers to motivation, he is referencing the "exciting" capacity of external stimuli, not the impulses prompted by internal need. The sharpness of James' theory fades when the next question is asked. Yes, external stimuli excite, but what is it inside of us that causes us to care enough to (1) be excited, and (2) to react one way and not another? James notes that the body (mysteriously?) has "a mind of its own" and this suggests that we have more of an active core than what James allows. Elsewhere, he states that we love adulation, we desire to please, and we are ambitions and vain. These well-known human traits are not reactive, but inner needs that motivate us to go out into the world and seek interaction with external objects in particular ways.

James' theory does not allow for an inner "given" human being because, it might be speculated, this does not provide sufficient flexibility for us to become what James would hope we might become. Again, he says, objects and thoughts of objects motivate our reaction, and pleasure and pain reinforce or inhibit how we react. This view is at odds with Schopenhauer and Darwin's view that not only do we have a common life impulse (Will, survival), we also have a relatively fixed character that defines (or provides a propensity for) what objects we seek and defend against and the level of energy that we apply to them. Our inner character defines a substantial collection of inner needs. These needs Schopenhauer says are "pain". They are something we want to be satisfied. Pain prompts our action in the world, both seeking and reacting, to satisfy need. When we are successful in seeking or reacting, we experience pleasure and then actions stop until the life force within pops up again (e.g., hunger, sex, need to affirm group membership and one's value within the group). James disagrees. He rejects Schopenhauer's "determinism" of "fixed character" and goes on to say that "The problem with the man is less what act he shall now resolve to do than what being he shall now choose to become." As what that "man" might be, it is not for the weak-minded and sentimental type. Rather, it is the "heroic man" who by "pure inward willingness....makes himself one of the masters and the lords of life."

James' view regarding the role of mind to guide behavior is not inaccurate. That is the evolutionary role for mind. However, the ends that the mind serves are relatively fixed (generally, survival ends and well-being, and by variable character traits that help define how each of us more specifically interact with the environment), and mind's role is to make choices about how these fixed biological needs will be met. Even with his admirable attempt to unite psychology with Darwinian biology, James nevertheless minimizes the role for relatively fixed biological ends, and he believes that we more or less have a blank slate to create ourselves. The alternative perspective outlined here suggests we are more anchored, for good and bad, than what James would allow. This is, perhaps, a more realistic assessment of who we are and who we are able to become.

132 reviews13 followers
March 6, 2017
This is a classic because it is one of the first published books on psychology as a discipline and because it is full of James' ideas about how the mind works solely based on the method of introspection. I read this when I was in graduate school one summer the 100th anniversary of its being publishd and I am so grateful I was given that opportunity because its amazing the amount of insight in this volume as well as the second one. It takes a while to adjust to the slight differences in his language (the way he uses the word "brain" often does not exactly refer to the material brain for example) but it is a wonderful and worthwhile read. There are certain passages of this work a student of psychology often runs in to but SO much more when read from cover to cover.
20 reviews
October 22, 2007
I started reading this book because he gets referenced alot... there seems to be a pretty avid following of his also... but I have yet to find that ingenuity.... the reading is pretty tough so I'm probably missing alot of stuff
Profile Image for JP.
1,163 reviews40 followers
May 18, 2013
It's the first modern form of truly scientific psychological analysis. He also builds from a knowledge of philosophy and later in his life focused very much on that.
26 reviews
Read
September 11, 2014
I must read it again.; so difficult to retain all the information. His style is hard to follow. Maybe I should give up psychology!
Displaying 1 - 29 of 29 reviews

Can't find what you're looking for?

Get help and learn more about the design.