Jump to ratings and reviews
Rate this book

Psychology Press & Routledge Classic Editions

The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception

Rate this book
This is a book about how we see: the environment around us (its surfaces, their layout, and their colors and textures); where we are in the environment; whether or not we are moving and, if we are, where we are going; what things are good for; how to do things (to thread a needle or drive an automobile); or why things look as they do.
The basic assumption is that vision depends on the eye which is connected to the brain. The author suggests that natural vision depends on the eyes in the head on a body supported by the ground, the brain being only the central organ of a complete visual system. When no constraints are put on the visual system, people look around, walk up to something interesting and move around it so as to see it from all sides, and go from one vista to another. That is natural vision -- and what this book is about.

332 pages, Paperback

First published January 1, 1979

Loading interface...
Loading interface...

About the author

James J. Gibson

15 books37 followers
James Jerome Gibson is one of the most important psychologists of the 20th century, best known for his work on visual perception. He received his Ph.D. from Princeton University and his first major work was The Perception of the Visual World (1950) in which he rejected behaviorism for a view based on his own experimental work.

In his later works, including The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (1979), Gibson became more philosophical and criticized cognitivism in the same way he had attacked behaviorism before, arguing strongly in favor of direct perception and direct realism, as opposed to cognitivist indirect realism. He termed his new approach "ecological psychology".

Gibson’s legacy is increasingly influential on many contemporary movements in psychology, particularly those considered to be post-cognitivist.

Ratings & Reviews

What do you think?
Rate this book

Friends & Following

Create a free account to discover what your friends think of this book!

Community Reviews

5 stars
119 (49%)
4 stars
82 (34%)
3 stars
32 (13%)
2 stars
7 (2%)
1 star
1 (<1%)
Displaying 1 - 22 of 22 reviews
Profile Image for Trevor.
1,340 reviews22.7k followers
October 19, 2020
I want to start with the argument that a large part of the reason we read books is that that it gives us an opportunity to see into the minds of people and therefore to see that they don’t necessarily think in the same ways we do. And I know, that is supposed to be always true, no matter who we read, but you know, often when I read books I think – yeah, I could have written that. I couldn’t say that about this book. The point is that there are a few times when I read a book that I know my brain and this other person’s brain simply don’t function in anything like the same way. And getting to see that is a large part of the pleasure of reading their book.

Mostly I feel like this when the writer reminds me of Aristotle. Don’t get me wrong – there is part of me that would love to think like Aristotle. And I love to watch that style of thinking unfold in all its elegance, in its ordered, clear, concise and devastatingly logical structure – it is like watching one of David Hockney’s iPad art drawings suddenly appear – I can like it all I like, but I also know I’ll never be able to replicate one of those drawings myself. The joy of appreciation for what I’m seeing is simply not born out of an anticipation of ever being able to give it all a go myself.

In this book Gibson is seeking to understand how we see. And he had a good reason for trying to understand that. He was teaching pilots how to land planes, something their visual perception systems hadn’t evolved to do or make sense of, and so he needed to create simulators that would allow them to ‘experience’ the visual aspects of landing a plane and therefore be able to practice that skill in a safe way, but also in a way that would ‘show’ them what that experience actually ‘looked’ like.

The problem is that we have been trained by Western visual artistic traditions to think of seeing as ultimately like seeing the world as if it was a painting – that is to see the world as if we only had one eye and that eye was forced to squint through a knot-hole in a wooden fence. We think we see whole images, in much the same way that paintings work, and paintings work by recreating the perception of a three-dimensional image as if you were stuck at a fixed focal point in that three-dimensional world. Not that that, in itself, isn’t an incredibly interesting and impressive thing to achieve. It is just that that isn’t how our visual system works virtually all of the time.

The first thing to notice about our visual system is that we don’t see the world from a fixed vantage point, but rather that we are constantly in motion. Our eyes are rarely at a fixed location – well, other than when we are in ‘screen time’ mode. When we observe the world we don’t just observe it with a fixed lens, but rather with our entire bodies. If we can’t make something out on first glance, we can move toward or away from it, we can shift our head to the right, jump up and down and so on. But it isn’t just that we can move our body to give our eyes a better vantage-point that explains Gibson’s point here. Instead, the fact that we move through space is one of the most important ways in which we get to understand space at all – to see it. Our moving bodies is what makes visual perception what it is – moving is not an accidental feature of our visual system, but the core to understanding how we see. When we move the stuff that is furthest from us stays fixed, the things closer to us moves in relation to this fixed background. Such changes mean that what we see is occluding edges appearing and disappearing and this slow appearance and disappearance of things from view gives us a means to understand our position within an environment – and this is part of the reason why Gibson refers to his model of visual perception as being ‘ecological’. Our eyes aren’t what we see with in this environment – our visual perception system here is our entire body – because it is only our eyes in motion that allows us to perceive the world.

The other reason this is an ‘ecological’ model is because Gibson sees our visual perception as being interested in understanding the ‘affordances’ of the environment we find ourselves in. Affordance is the word he uses for the potential uses of the various objects we find in an environment, and it is these uses (can I walk on this? Can I use it to hit something? To throw at my attacker? And so on) that help us to understand how the brain constructs visual perception not just as a window onto the world, but to engage with (live within) the environments we find ourselves within.

There is far too much information in this book for someone like me who, let’s be honest, is never going to need to understand the workings of the human visual perception system in anything like the detail that this book provides. But this isn’t the real pleasure of reading this book, rather it is like reading Aristotle. The way we are lead through this discussion, the way each element of the argument builds on the last, making clear that how we think we see and how we actually see the world are different is a devastating tour through the logical development of an argument, but also how reason can be used to help us ‘see again’ beyond our preferred metaphors and understandings. Reading this book is a worthwhile exercise whether you are interested in understanding how we see or not. That is, visual perception is nearly (if not quite) a bit beside the point here. What this book does is provide a breathtaking example of precise and logical reasoning being allowed to unfold – and it is devastating to watch.
Profile Image for Alina.
320 reviews212 followers
September 22, 2021
(Review from my first read)

I consider this book a must-read for anyone interested in the nature of perception. Gibson introduces his theory of ecological affordances and establishes the field of Gibsonian ecological psychology in this book. He theorizes that visual perception consists of affordances, which are opportunities for action that are constituted by the interaction between an animal’s sensorimotor and bodily skills and the material or physical possibilities offered by the environment. His theory entails significances that objects and environmental structures manifest are immediately perceived, rather than inferred or arrived at through some other cognitive process.

Advice for potential readers in approaching this book: Gibson, as a psychologist, is highly readable. However, as a psychologist, many chapters are devoted to small empirical details, some of which are overly speculative and outdated. His overall theory, beyond these small details, remains highly accurate and fruitful for future adaptation and research, however. So, I would recommend that the really essential chapters of this books are the Introduction, "8. The Theory of Affordances," "3. The Meaningful Environment," and "4. The Relationship between Stimulation and Stimulus Information." Other chapters I found theoretically rich are "6. Events and the Information for Perceiving Events," "7. The Optical Information for Self-Perception," and "12. The Theory of Information Pickup and its Consequences".

As a summary of his core theory: Gibson argues that the detail and richness of perceptual experience is not the product of cognitive processes inside the brain. Instead, causal events in the mind-independent environment do much of the “work” in providing potential sensory detail, and an animal simply “samples” these elaborately structured details. Environmental structures and objects have exterior surfaces that reflect light waves, sound waves, and other types of oscillations that occur in transmission mediums, and determine diffraction patterns. Gibson calls these diffraction patterns that fill an animal’s ecological niche an ambient array. There are optic arrays, sonic arrays, and so on.

The textures, sizes, sturdiness, and other compositional features of object surfaces diffract oscillation waves in different manners. The layout of object surfaces in an environmental situation also diffract oscillation waves. There are invariant correspondences between ambient array patterns and types of object surfaces or layouts. Animals are equipped with bodily skills that enable them to “sample” ambient arrays (e.g. visual system accesses arrays of light waves) and directly perceive the particular objects, their unique compositional qualities, and their layout in the environment which determine the patterns in the ambient arrays. These skills are result of an animal species’ evolutionary adaptation in accordance to features of its relevant ecological niche.

Gibson also argues that animal behavior is determined by ecological affordances. Affordances are the opportunities for action inherent in the perception of environmental structures, from the perspective of an animal. For any given animal, the objects that populate its perceptual world are not mere physical structures but necessarily meaningful affordances that express potentialities for action. Animals don’t need to engage in voluntary or complex sensory or cognitive processes in order to figure out how to act in the world; affordances, which are immediately perceived, guide an organism’s behavior.

Objects can be affordances because the particular texture and other compositional features of their surfaces determine the diffraction patterns in the ambient array. The invariant correspondences between compositional feature types and diffraction patterns afford an animal to learn to immediately perceive the compositional features via detection of diffraction patterns. Gibson hypothesizes that because perceptual systems are capable of picking up on these invariant correspondences, they are also capable of picking up on more highly complex invariant correspondences, or “invariant combinations,” such as those between particular emotional effects, functions in sociocultural practices or any number of opportunities of action, and the diffraction patterns determined by particular surface compositional features of objects. Gibson implies that there is a sort of classical conditioning learning process animals undergo in order to gain the embodied skills that can access these more complex invariant combinations and amount to direct perception of the usefulness and significances of objects.

Affordances are neither mind-independent properties of the environment nor properties projected by an organism’s sensory or perceptual systems. Instead, they are the relations between particular aspects of an organism and aspects of its environment. Any mind-independent, material environment has infinite possible ways to be interacted on and manipulated. The particular animal at hand as finite skill sets, which determine the ways it can perceive its ecological niche and interact with it. Any affordance is possible because the material environment permits it, and the animal that perceives this affordance has the particular physiological capacities and learned skills that can access to environment in the relevant ways specified by the affordance.

_____

(Scattered thoughts from my second read)

Can we just say that there are two ways of defining perception: (1) as consisting in our five sensory modalities, and (2) as whatever (regardless of whether it’s in a sense-datum format) we apprehend, at a personal-level, in an automatic fashion? Only on (2) can we say that we "directly" perceive affordances. Otherwise, if we commit to (1), we could admit that there is subpersonal processing, the drawing of unconscious inferences, that is necessary for synthesizing the experience of affordances; and so when we consider the subpersonal level, and not only the phenomenological level, perception of afforadnces is not direct.

Gibson argues that our perceptual experience consists in both information about the invariant structures of objects and their visual appearances that vary in accordance with our movements in relation to them. The latter claim agrees with our traditional intuitions on what sorts of entities are admissible in perceptual experience: low-level sensory properties. But the former is more troubling. What exact form does the information about invariant structures of objects take on when we consciously encounter it in perception? Nanay might want to say this information is apprehended in the form of mental imagery, which is concurrent with visual appearances of the environment. But this isn’t our only option: perhaps we can think about encountering information that is disembodied of any visual format. But then in what form does this information occur in perception?

So Gibson admits into perception information that is generated by our sensitivity towards what is invariant—that which accounts for the systematic perspectival changes. We can thereby perceive these invariant structures. Given this commitment, what others kinds of information may also permitted for Gibson? Maybe there are embodied skills and internalized social norms that underpin and systematically govern which diverse meanings flow forward (Sartre's “nothingness” in Being and Nothingness); they are available in perceptual experience in an analogous way to invariant physical structures!

Alva Noe claims in Varieties of Presence that objects we could access given our skills show up, even if they're not physically visible. This specification of which feature of an object suffices for it's showing up perceptually is different from Gibson's. What we can access vs. what is invariant and accounting for the systematic changes. Given these different accounts of the conditions that an object needs to meet for it to show up in perception—do these apparently different accounts actually overlap? What are really the correct conditions to be identified—what kinds of objects are admissible in perception, and on what grounds?
48 reviews10 followers
Read
August 11, 2015
This was a fascinating read. Gibson walks you through a novel account of visual perception with rich, detailed explanations and a compelling narrative flow. I won't try to summarize the theory here, and while much of it is intuitively plausible I haven't engaged with the evidence or dug into the details nearly enough to have an opinion on its correctness, but some aspects I particularly appreciated:

* Gibson starts his framework on the level of analysis where the high level features of perception that we care about can be explained, rather than framing things in terms of physics.
* Gibson shows a strong handle on the problems of reifying abstractions, and uses that to drive many of the differences between his theory and the mainstream ones. For example, he drives home the point that planes, lines, and points are abstractions over surfaces and their relationships, and that we should not start by trying to reduce the latter to the former.
* Gibson neither shies away from philosophical approaches where appropriate nor substitutes philosophy for science.
* Gibson has engaged with the mainstream theories as an expert and clearly understands them well, using that understanding to inform his approach.
* The theory is radically different in many ways that, if nothing else, will help remind me that the current paradigms aren't the only way to consider these questions and that they oughtn't be taken for granted (even if they are in fact true and useful). In particular (and this applies to more than just perception), the book serves as an excellent example of the possibility of doing science outside of a reductionist framework.
* Gibson's framework has some really tantalizing possibilities for interesting integrations with my framework of concept formation and other abstract awareness.
* Gibson's approach is profoundly empirical. Not only is the exposition replete with references to existing research, it also makes explicit numerous explicit conclusions about what kinds of experiments should be fruitful and what kinds of evidence we ought to see. The theory is not just a reframing of existing theories with the same ultimate results. I don't know if Gibson is right, but I know I can check

That being said, I did have some concerns. Primarily, the framework presented radically diverges from how I've learned and thought about perception, and as a result even with the detailed descriptions and caveats and contrasts with traditional ideas I had a hard time fully integrating the ideas and getting a sense of the larger structure. This is of course unfair, and probably not something that could be done any better in a single book, but still detracted for me. I think the only real solution here is to dive into the literature that he built his ideas from and try to see how I could build them myself, as unfortunately Gibson died shortly after publication and I've heard some very mixed things about those who came after. I also found the degree of his dismissiveness of those who accept the mainstream theories (in fairness, including his former self) both much stronger than was justified by his presentation and indicative of a potential failure to take into account the ways in which those theories might inform his, even if they're wrong.
Profile Image for Sean.
14 reviews
March 8, 2008
Dense stuff. The radicality of his thesis gets lost a bit in its common-sense logic. Basically, he is arguing against a laboratory-based model of "the eye being stimulated." In its place he proposes an experience-based theory of perception -- i.e. not seeing but looking. Well, that at least is the best way for me to sum it up in one sentence; it's complicated.

Interesting, but not exactly beach reading (it took me a LOOONG time to get through this one, stopping several times to read other books).
Profile Image for Geoffreyjen.
Author 1 book18 followers
March 30, 2021
One of the basic referents of my own scientific career and also one of the most widely influential books of the 20th century. James J. Gibson's book is still fresh, and still gaining in importance, as the world of science slowly shifts towards his way of thinking about the world. Essentially, he saw action not as a separate event of process, but as a mutually grounded function within both person/organism/agent and the environment. A must read for any scientist, indeed, any person interested in the workings of the world.
Profile Image for Mark Moon.
150 reviews109 followers
January 6, 2018
Many sections in this book read like unedited research notes, not suitable for publication in book form - but don't let that distract you. The ecological approach to visual perception was a radically novel proposal 40 years ago, and many of the concepts it introduced are still of great relevance today. The embodied cognition programme in psychology owes a great deal to it, and the affordance-centric approach to perception is a common idea in modern robotics.

Some of the main idea in this book are that 1) vision is a perceptual system that cannot be understood in terms of the eyes to the exclusion of the motor system whereby visual perceivers explore their environment, and 2) that the two-dimensional pattern of light that falls on the retina at any time (the so-called "retinal image", which is not really an image in the sense that it can't be looked at) is not remotely like that which is perceived at that time. The essence of Gibson's "direct perception" thesis, at least in the form I'm most comfortable accepting, is that percepts have more structural features in common with the objects in the world they are supposed to be percepts of, than with the raw sensory data (in the case of vision, the retinal signal) by means of which they are perceived.

(Another idea that I found interesting is that of the "occluding edge" - a visual edge that indicate that one surface is partially hidden by another - because the progressive accretion or deletion of one texture, contrasted with the preservation of the other, provides key information for determining which surface is hiding the other.)
Profile Image for Thomas Lønn Hammer.
310 reviews60 followers
July 29, 2022
Essentially an elaboration on Heideggers ideas of embodiment, ready-at-hand etc - without giving any credit. Explains the world in terms of how it is experienced for various organisms, contrary to the abstract "world" of physics. Overly pedagogical. Can skip a lot and get the gist of it.

In terms of 'meta-worldviews' though, ecological ontology is definitely where it's at, compared to physicalist ontology.
Profile Image for akemi.
454 reviews169 followers
Currently reading
April 26, 2022
perception is not a passive impression, a tracing of the world, like a death mask, onto the brain

perception is a mobilisation, a coming and going, active, shifting, bodily, preemptive of thought and representation

the knowledge of nonthought in the curve of reaching, the flick of the eyes combined with the neck and legs tilting locomoting along a ground whose arc meets the sky in an infinity line



But the other person has a surface that reflects light, and the information to specify what he or she is, invites, promises, threatens, or does can be found in the light.


it's, unfortunately (and unsurprisingly), a very ocularcentric lifeworld that gibson paints. there are beautiful passages here about luminous affordances, but i would love to read a blind scholar's response to this work
April 24, 2022
“An Ecological Approach to Visual Perception”, by James Gibson, challenges the common belief that we see with our brain. Gibson does not deny the fact that our eyes are connected to our brain and the optic nerves send signals to it. He dethrones the idea that our eyes work like cameras and send pictures to our brain to interpret. He argues that seeing is not a complex analysis done by our brain to interpret the light that penetrates our eyes. He first starts by detailing the basic component of vision, the optical array. According to Gibson, we see and understand the world by experiencing changes in the optical array and learning what a certain change in our optical array signifies from an early age. For example, a moving object will take up more and more space, in the optical array we see, if it is approaching. Gibson analyzes and responds to many previously conceived theories of visual perception and proposes how they are wrong by compared to his ecological approach. The ecological approach stipulates that we see with our eyes, on our head, with our head on our body, and our body on the ground, and our body can move to occupy different places of perception. Gibson backs all his claims with studies he and other professors conducted to prove that surfaces and solid angles are the components by which we recognize things in the environment. According to Gibson, the significance of affordance (what the environment offers the animal, what it provides or furnishes, either for good or ill), can also experience through what our eyes as an organ sees and is not processed by our brain, like a machine, to understand. “An Ecological Approach to Visual Perception”, is a tremendously interesting book and it was astonishing to realize how our knowledge of visual perception has advanced.
Profile Image for Alexander Van Leadam.
279 reviews2 followers
November 17, 2019
In this book Gibson continues the development of his ecological approach to psychology. His emphasis remains on information and animal-environment interaction but quite refreshingly he is explicit about how his ideas evolved, including rejecting earlier formulations, explanations and assumptions. In this respect, the book is invaluable in reading Gibson. Some chapters are rather repetitive but not disturbingly so. In the end, the reader should have a much clearer view of how visual perception works in reality, beyond laboratory conditions and intriguing demostrations. One of the most modern elements of Gibson's approach is the debunking of geometry and other implementation mechanisms that detach us from true experience and distort our understanding of real phenomena. The chapters on pictures and moving pictures are excellent examples of the transparency one can achieve through this way of reasoning.
November 15, 2023
I wonder what this guy would say today based on current research. Would assume he’d change a lot of what he wrote to form a more constructivist view, but the information here is honestly amazing. Love how he tries to bring in physics and psychology together. This is the first I’ve read about invariants and affordances, will be thinking about it for the rest of my life. Maybe it’s a little painful the details he gets down to, but it’s for the good of explaining the concepts as best as he can. Would recommend this book to just about anyone concerned with perception or phenomenology
Profile Image for Joe.
106 reviews1 follower
March 21, 2020
Groundbreaking work. This is truly a classic in the fields of psychology and perception. He breaks down many of the accepted notions of visual perception (gestalt/sensory and stimulatory response) with thoughtful insights and experimental interpretations. I only wish that experimental validation of the theories had been presented, as well. Guess I'll have to go digging through citations...
Profile Image for Kit.
222 reviews2 followers
Shelved as 'to-read-per'
February 17, 2020
Recommend by Jordan Peterson in his 3017 Maps of Meaning Lecture 06, posted 2/21/17. Peterson thinks Gibson’s fundamental conclusion is wrong, but that the whole book is brilliant!
Profile Image for Wangdo Kim.
20 reviews1 follower
April 1, 2019
We cannot change it. Why has man changed the shapes and substances of his environment? To change what it affords him. He has made more available what benefits him and less pressing what injures him. In making life easier for himself, of course, he has made life harder for most of the other animals. We all fit into the substructures of the environment in our various ways, for we were all, in fact, formed by them. We were created by the world we live in.

Gibson said that if what we perceived were the entities of physics and mathematics, meaning would have to be imposed on them. But if what we perceived are the entities of environment science, their meaning can be discovered. He has conceived "the theory of affordances". He has described the environment as the surfaces that separate substances from the medium in which the animals live. But he has also described what the environment affords animals, mentioning the terrain, shelters, water, fire, objects, tool, other animals, and human displays. The import question is how do we go from surfaces to affordance? A radical hypothesis implies that the values and meanings of things in the environment can be directly perceived, moreover, it would explain the sense in which values and meaning are external to the perceiver.

The advantage to the theory of perception to be derived from a study of this affordance is apparent at every step. We may in our perception-action coupling space conceive quadratic forms like those of the conics, follow Joachimsthal's equation, in connection with maximization and minimization problem in motor control, and observed that if we adopt the fertile method of investigation introduced by Joachimsthal, an equilibrium equation of locomotion and manipulation arose in connection with the determination of existence of quadratic function.
Profile Image for Robert St.Amant.
Author 2 books4 followers
May 27, 2012
Pick up a hammer. How did you know which end to pick up? It's not necessarily experience or intelligence; toddlers do the same with their toy tools, as well as chimpanzees in laboratory experiments. And how do you know what it's possible to do with the hammer? Again, it's not necessarily experience or intelligence; some animals as simple as wasps use small pebbles to hammer down the earth.

James Gibson, a vision psychologist, develops a theory in this book about how people (and other animals) can determine what it's possible to do, based on his concept of affordance. He writes,

The affordances of the environment are what it offers the animal, what it provides or furnishes, either for good or ill. The verb to afford is found in the dictionary, but the noun affordance is not. I have made it up. I mean by it something that refers to both the environment and the animal in a way that no existing term does. It implies the complementarity of the animal and the environment.

Gibson's concept of affordance has a natural appeal, and it has been adopted (or adapted) in many fields, from user interaction design to robotics. (Though its scientific underpinnings still remain in dispute. Many dismiss the idea because a plausible visual or cognitive mechanism for identifying affordances has not yet been identified, but others, especially in the subfield of ecological psychology, still pursue the idea with new theories and experiments.) It's sometimes a bit frustrating, in that so many details are missing, but it's a worthwhile read.
Profile Image for Leif.
1,749 reviews92 followers
December 8, 2015
The legend never dies. Here's a little snippet, a footnote that gestures toward the tenor of Gibson's writing:
Ever since someone peeled off the back of the excised eye of a slaughtered ox and, holding it up in front of a scene, observed a tiny, coloured, inverted image of the scene on the transparent retina, we have been tempted to draw a false conclusion. We think of the image as something to be seen, a picture on a screen. You can see it if you take out the ox’s eye, so why shouldn’t the ox see it? The fallacy ought to be evident.
An iconoclast, and a pace-setter for neurobiological and psychological researchers after him.
Profile Image for Scott.
66 reviews5 followers
March 27, 2010
A very dense argument about our notion of perception and how we see the world. I was especially interested in Gibson's explanation of "Affordance Theory" which is relevant to some of my current research.
Profile Image for Brandon.
14 reviews1 follower
March 21, 2007
J.J. reset the standard with this classic. If you want to know how we do what we do in our visual environment, give it a read.
Profile Image for Dinesh Jayaraman.
36 reviews46 followers
Shelved as 'to-resume'
May 25, 2017
Gibson thinks psychology has developed a little physics envy as it tries to become a legit science. In the process, it has lost its intuitions about the basic settings in which perception happens.

The first portion of the book is just Gibson trying to put words to our intuitive understanding of our environments, as opposed to a physicist's understanding. This is dry stuff.
Displaying 1 - 22 of 22 reviews

Can't find what you're looking for?

Get help and learn more about the design.