I suspect that this is THE book to read if you want to understand multiverse (or many worlds) theory. Wallace is thorough, precise, technical, and formal. And the subject matter is fascinating.
Hugh Everett was a Princeton Physics PhD student when he developed the “Everett Interpretation” of quantum mechanics, now known as the multiverse theory, or the many worlds theory. Despite support from John Wheeler, Everett got a cold reception from the physics world for his published papers and actually left academic science for a commercial career after completing his PhD.
In more recent years, the Everett Interpretation has gained credibility in the physics world, and Wallace’s treatment gives some good answers to account for its resurgence.
The traditionally dominant Copenhagen Interpretation of quantum theory has a problem with realism. It’s not even a sophisticated philosophical problem. It just doesn’t seem to render what’s really going on at the quantum level understandable, at least not in conceptual or visualizable terms. Even theorists we commonly associate with quantum mechanics, like Schrödinger, or more recently Richard Feynman, have said as much.
Wallace’s account of the Everett Interpretation aims to restore realism to quantum theory. Wallace, who has very enviable facility in both theoretical physics and philosophy of science, undertakes two daunting tasks — a detailed mathematical elaboration of the Everett interpretation itself, and a defense of realism at the quantum level when understood by that interpretation.
I should say before I go on that I’m not a physicist. My academic background is in philosophy, and, although I have certainly studied philosophy of science, a lot of this is new and uncomfortable to me. So I’m sure my account (of both Wallace and Everett) will have mistakes — hopefully they will be quibbles, not howlers. I’ll try to stick to my most solid ground.
Everett’s core idea is actually fairly straightforward. Schrödinger’s wavefunction provides successful mathematical tools for calculating and predicting behaviors of particles at the quantum level.
But it does so in terms of probabilities — the attributes of particles are expressed as objective probabilities. We cannot say what a particle’s spin or momentum or position, for example, is, only what possible values those attributes may have, and what weights or probabilities to attach to those possible values.
It’s not until a measurement is made that those attributes take on determinant values. Upon measurement, the quantum wavefunction “collapses” to a determinant state.
Wallace stresses, as has traditionally been maintained in the Copenhagen and other interpretations, that the indeterminacy prior to measurement is not epistemic, it is objective. It’s not that the particle’s spin is unknown, for example, but that the particle’s spin is objectively undetermined until the measurement takes place.
That leads traditionally to what is called the “measurement problem.” Why would a measurement determine the values of a particle’s attributes, and what becomes of all the possible but unrealized values the attributes had prior to measurement?
On Wallace’s account, the Everett Interpretation doesn’t solve the measurement problem, it eliminates it. All of the possible values for the particle’s attributes are realized. The measurement changes nothing.
The catch of course is that while all of the values are realized, they are realized in different “worlds” (or “universes”). Each possible value represents a branching of reality upon its realization. If a particle’s spin has possible values of up and down, both are realized in subsequently different branches of reality.
Straightforward but mind-boggling. We’ve rid ourselves of the nasty measurement problem, but we got the multiverse in trade.
Some readers, like some physicists, will bail at this point. Wallace, following Everett, has posited the existence of an indefinitely large number of universes (the terms “universe” and “world” are kind of awkwardly used interchangeably) — indefinitely large given that our reality is after all quantum reality, and the branchings are going to take place and compound upon one another on a literally countless scale.
Those universes do not interact, or technically may do so only very minimally. For all intents and purposes, there are countless independently existing universes, following their own courses, themselves producing new branchings and new universes.
You and I exist in countless of those universes, as branchings happen from the universe we are currently in. We experience only one — we are “branch-bound” in Wallace’s term, but we are instances among countless instances of ourselves across the multiverse.
Wallace says, “The ‘actual physical Universe’ is the multiply branching structure generated by unitary evolution under the Schrödinger equation. The branch weights are physical features of the structure; they are represented mathematically with the quantum wavefunction.”
It’s critical to Wallace’s argument that what Everett offers is a “literal” interpretation of quantum mechanics, in some sense the simplest interpretation. He even balks at the term “interpretation,” preferring its use restricted to such accounts as the Copenhagen Interpretation that add something to quantum mechanics (to Schrödinger’s wavefunction) rather that taking it “literally” as he believes the Everettian quantum theory does.
I would have liked to hear a little more discussion from Wallace of what constitutes a “literal” interpretation of a mathematical equation like Schrödinger’s, especially given how central the claim is to his argument.
That is the core idea, and the remainder of Wallace’s book is elaboration and defense of the Everett Interpretation. The longest treatment is a formal construction of the notion of “probability” in an Everettian universe, in which Wallace claims advantages for Everettian theory over the Copenhagen and other interpretations, as well as over classical physics itself.
Throughout, Wallace’s strategy is to show that what may appear paradoxical or weird about quantum theory as a whole is mitigated by Everettian multiverse theory, and that any apparent paradoxes or weirdness generated by Everettian physics itself dissolve under scrutiny or at least pale by comparison to alternatives.
Of course, there’s still the elephant in the room (or the many elephants in many rooms). That idea of “many worlds” or the “multiverse.”
I can’t even come close to presuming to pass judgment on Everettian theory, or on Wallace’s account of it, but here are some areas I’m left puzzling about. I know this review is going to get long, so I’ll try to be brief, especially since I don’t have answers, just questions.
Ontology:
Occam's Razor tells us that "entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity." But Occam’s Razor doesn’t always cut cleanly. Wallace would have it that the Everett universe has the advantage in that it doesn’t require the existence of unrealized probabilities, but it does so, arguably, at the cost of multiplying entities indefinitely, across its “many” worlds. I don’t think there’s a clear winner on the Occam scale.
Maybe more importantly, I’m unsure what to make of the notion of an Everettian “world.” In keeping with his emphasis on realism, Wallace treats the branched worlds of Everettian physics as physical, not logical worlds. The very physical world we live in right now is one of those Everettian worlds. To ask “where” the others are places a pretty severe stress on the word “where” since they aren’t anywhere in our universe.
Wallace asks us though to consider that the Everett universe is not so strange after all. For example, the extension of reality into “many worlds” is not so different from the expansion of our concept of space — once we considered the solar system to be the universe, but now we’ve expanded that concept to encompass countless solar systems in countless galaxies.
But the extension that the Everett universe requires is of a different kind — it’s not an expansion of the concept of physical space, it’s an uncontrolled multiplication of discrete, non-interacting physical spaces.
Personal Identity:
Each of us experiences continuous existence in only one Everettian world — we are, as Wallace says, branch-bound.
But there are indefinitely many worlds in which “I” also exist, alongside the one I experience. And, as time goes along, with more branching, there will be more and more “me’s” populating them. All of those “me’s” will continue a first person experience, in multiple branches of the future, but first person experience itself is singular, not multiple, so only one of those branches will be experienced by (this) me.
Our branch-boundedness guarantees that nothing really changes in terms of our singular first person experience. As Wallace says, “Despite appearances, the branching structure of Everettian quantum mechanics has few or no consequences for our everyday beliefs and actions.”
It is only from a “God’s eye view” that there are multiple me’s in multiple branches, with their own first person experiences.
Some ethical questions struggle to rise up. What are my responsibilities to those branched versions of myself, or the branched versions of other persons? Once branched, each is responsible for its own future, but, in the future branchings, my actions now have consequences for all of my branched selves and the branched selves of everyone I affect in my present world.
Testability:
Since the many worlds of Everettian physics don’t interact and aren’t directly detectable (see exception below), there is no sense in which we can detect the presence of other worlds than our own, or detect effects events in our own world could have on those others. We don’t directly observe branchings, and once branched, other worlds continue separately and independently.
Testability — some way in which we can observe and test whether the branching actually happens — is a core element of scientific method. I wouldn’t be the first to point out this weakness in multiverse theory.
This is where Wallace’s insistence that Everettian theory is a literal interpretation of quantum mechanics needs to bear weight. He, I think, would have it that the burden of proof lies not on Everettian theory but on other interpretations of quantum mechanics that add such features as wavefunction collapse or hidden variables. As he says, “. . . the Everett interpretation just is quantum mechanics. If you’re after some experiment to distinguish Everett-interpreted quantum mechanics from an operational interpretation of quantum mechanics [i.e., a non-realist interpretation], then sure, I haven’t got anything to offer.”
Given that, according to Wallace, Everettian theory is a literal interpretation of quantum mechanics, all tests of quantum mechanics are for him tests of Everettian theory. Therefore, Everettian theory is testable, despite our inability to directly detect the presence of the many worlds it predicts.
The one exception to the indetectability of other Everettian worlds, by the way, is discussed by Wallace in Chapter 10, specifically in a discussion of David Deutsch’s work on neutron interference. I admit I wasn’t fully able to follow that discussion. More homework for me.
Probability:
Remember that this is an attempt to construct a “realist” interpretation of quantum theory
Part II of the book is an extensive construction of probability in an Everett universe.
I won’t (and couldn’t reliably) go into the detail. The gist is that Wallace believes that Everettian quantum theory can not only make proper sense of the probabilities of events, but do so in a way that is in some respects superior to classical physics or non-Everettian quantum theory.
Intuitively, I can see it arguable that, since all non-zero probabilities are realized in the Everettian universe, there is a superior sense to the ‘reality” of those probabilities than for a universe in which some of those non-zero probabilities are not realized and simply vanish.
The suspicion I had about probability going into Wallace’s discussion was this: Schrödinger’s wavefunction contains weights assigned to potential attributes of a particle, awaiting realization by measurement. If we interpret those weights as probabilities (e.g., that the spin of a particle will be measured with one value rather than another), as is normally done (and as Wallace does under Everettian quantum theory), what effect do those probabilities have on branching? For example, do higher probability outcomes produce more worlds with that outcome that lower probability ones?
But Wallace has ruled out, for reasons I won’t go into and don’t fully understand, counting worlds — thus there is no sense in which there are “more” worlds with higher probability outcomes than lower probability ones.
So the problem, phrased in the way that I just did to anticipate some such resolution, is a pseudo-problem.
What becomes of probability in an Everettian universe is exactly what one would want to become of it — for any observer, the weights in the wavefunction can be interpreted as the likelihood that that observer will obtain the relevant value for the particle’s attribute when measured. The existence of other branched observers subsequent to the measurement is irrelevant to that observer’s own experience.
Measurement:
The dissolution of the measurement problem is one of the chief advantages that Wallace sees with Everettian theory. No wavefunction collapse, no magic happening when a measurement takes place, because all possible values of the measurement are realized, just in branched worlds.
Fine. But I’m still left with a question. Does the branching take place when measurement takes place? If so, although the measurement doesn’t generate a wavefunction collapse, it does seem to generate branching.
I may be misunderstanding the relationship between measurement and branching, so the gap here may be my own.
I’ve gone on for a long time. This is obviously a fascinating, provocative book. I’d dare anyone to read it and not be challenged by it.
I can’t say Im convinced — after all, my understanding of what I would be convinced of has a lot of gaps. But I won’t stop thinking about this.
I should mention that there are more accessible treatments of Everettian theory out there. See Sean Carroll’s Something Deeply Hidden for example. Wallace’s book is challenging not only conceptually but technically — his treatment is formal and mathematical.