Jump to ratings and reviews
Rate this book

Nonsense on Stilts: How to Tell Science from Bunk

Rate this book

Recent polls suggest that fewer than 40 percent of Americans believe in Darwin’s theory of evolution, despite it being one of science’s best-established findings. More and more parents are refusing to vaccinate their children for fear it causes autism, though this link can been consistently disproved. And about 40 percent of Americans believe that the threat of global warming is exaggerated, despite near consensus in the scientific community that manmade climate change is real.

Why do people believe bunk? And what causes them to embrace such pseudoscientific beliefs and practices? Noted skeptic Massimo Pigliucci sets out to separate the fact from the fantasy in this entertaining exploration of the nature of science, the borderlands of fringe science, and—borrowing a famous phrase from philosopher Jeremy Bentham—the nonsense on stilts. Presenting case studies on a number of controversial topics, Pigliucci cuts through the ambiguity surrounding science to look more closely at how science is conducted, how it is disseminated, how it is interpreted, and what it means to our society. The result is in many ways a “taxonomy of bunk” that explores the intersection of science and culture at large.

No one—not the public intellectuals in the culture wars between defenders and detractors of science nor the believers of pseudoscience themselves—is spared Pigliucci’s incisive analysis. In the end, Nonsense on Stilts is a timely reminder of the need to maintain a line between expertise and assumption. Broad in scope and implication, it is also ultimately a captivating guide for the intelligent citizen who wishes to make up her own mind while navigating the perilous debates that will affect the future of our planet.

338 pages, Paperback

First published January 1, 2008

Loading interface...
Loading interface...

About the author

Massimo Pigliucci

73 books1,011 followers
Massimo Pigliucci is an author, blogger, podcaster, as well as the K.D. Irani Professor of Philosophy at the City College of New York.

His academic work is in evolutionary biology, philosophy of science, the nature of pseudoscience, and practical philosophy. His books include How to Be a Stoic: Using Ancient Philosophy to Live a Modern Life (Basic Books) and Nonsense on Stilts: How to Tell Science from Bunk (University of Chicago Press).

His new book is The Quest for Character: What the Story of Socrates and Alcibiades Teaches Us about Our Search for Good Leaders (Basic Books). More by Massimo at https://newstoicism.org.

Ratings & Reviews

What do you think?
Rate this book

Friends & Following

Create a free account to discover what your friends think of this book!

Community Reviews

5 stars
345 (30%)
4 stars
481 (42%)
3 stars
226 (19%)
2 stars
59 (5%)
1 star
34 (2%)
Displaying 1 - 30 of 95 reviews
Profile Image for Rich.
12 reviews1 follower
June 2, 2010
Too many books by skeptics involve shooting fish in a barrel; content to point out the foolishness of clearly fringe beliefs and stroke the egos of those readers who already view themselves as critical thinking advocates of science.
Nonsense on Stilts is NOT one of those books.

Rather, it is a far ranging look at the nature of science itself. Pigliucci manages to include a discussion of hard vs. soft science, the role of public intellectuals, an introduction to the problem of induction, a conceptual history of science's origins from the pre-socratics to modern day, an overview of the philosophy of science from Popper to Bayesianism, a discussion of evaluating expertise in a field, and a critique of postmodernist views. And he does so without seeming digressive. All of these topics are presented with the sharp focus of shedding light on what science is and is not, how science is practiced, and how the reader can separate real science from nonsense. Nonsense on Stilts is an excellent introductory overview that covers a lot of ground without bogging down in technicalities. Pigliucci doesn't just de-bunk popular non-science like ID creationism and climate change denialism, he discusses them along with borderline scientific views and clear examples of science with a view towards understanding the bigger picture of scientific inquiry. The book isn't pollyannaish cheerleading for that simplistic (and wrong) view of scientific method you were likely taught in grade school. It is an introductory survey of science studies and philosophy of science which is as relevant for someone who is already a science advocate as for someone who is an unfortunate believer in 'bunk'.
Profile Image for Theresa.
183 reviews40 followers
October 12, 2015
As far as skeptics go, I prefer mine avuncular and approachable like Carl Sagan as opposed to prickly and aloof like Richard Dawkins; so I thought this was marvelous. Pigliucci is maybe not exactly as warm and turtleneck-y as Carl Sagan, but that's not meant to be a stab at either one of them; just the main difference.

I really enjoyed this and definitely want to check out some of the other things he's written. I love it when I find somebody who writes good stuff and isn't dead yet. *high fives*
Profile Image for Andrew Skretvedt.
87 reviews22 followers
October 31, 2014
(unedited and lightly proofed)

I found this book well worth reading, esp. the last 30 pages or so. I withheld two stars from my rating mostly for what didn't happen in Chapter 6. If you're short on time, here's a shortcut approach to getting the book's chief take-away:

Start with Chapter 11, § "Science as a Bayesian Algorithm" (page 275 in the edition I read from), and read from there through Chapter 12 and the Conclusion. That'll be about 31 pages. The essence of the book and its take-away for readers is right there. Glance at the footnotes for that portion too. After this, if you're wanting more depth, rewind to the beginning and start. Otherwise, you'll have the most important bit and will be primed to think about Goldman's Five Criteria when evaluating the judgements of experts you may be exposed to, no matter what the topic of interest. That will serve you quite well. This last part of the book is really the only part that to me affirmatively addressed the statement in the subtitle, "How to tell science from bunk." That there wasn't more to flesh out the premise of the subtitle perhaps was also a reason I withheld some stars.

As for the rest of the book, I felt there was somewhat less than I wanted on the philosophy of science and science-vs.-pseudoscience. The types of logical fallacy are important, and didn't get much more than an incidental treatment here. I need bolstering in this area myself, and didn't get it here. Types of logical fallacy seem to show up very often in arguments portrayed in media, so having a toolkit for this would help in making quick evaluation of what some "news" program's analyst or magazine article's author is trying to sell you.

The history of the development of science is interesting backstory, and worth including, but I think if other parts of this book were edited down to make room for it, I would have appreciated a different cut.



That's about it for the hard review. In the remaining space, I'm going to talk about a silent parade of elephants that sit quietly among you as you read Chapter 6, which is good, but could really be a whole book in itself if you wanted to address said elephants. As it is, the author pretty much confines himself to an orthodox narrative and leaves the elephants unaddressed (perhaps he wasn't even aware of them).

Chapter 6 addresses the relationship of science and politics by focusing on the global warming issue, which is too bad in my view, because this issue has too much baggage attached to it for many lay readers, myself included, and as a result it makes too narrow a survey of the relationships between them.

There is much more to say about the relationship of politics and science, and I won't touch on any of it except to suggest that this alliance of politics and science (where it gets the majority of its funding now, a relatively recent innovation for good or ill) is a key reason behind the anti-intellectualism addressed in the book. "Scientific American" magazine, for example, today could be regarded more as a public-policy advocacy magazine which derives its authority from the science it portrays, rather than a magazine devoted to the promotion of science, and dissemination of its discoveries. The politically focused parts of the magazine have become dominant over the pure science articles. The pure science features have also been cut down in length and scope to make room for the political, with more reliance on freelancing science writers over the researchers themselves, who used to write up their own features more often.

When the name of science is used to justify political ends, and those ends run counter to basic human liberties, or even simple expectations about the role of government in a polity, the resentment for the politic bleeds over into a mistrust of science too. Science then gets tossed out wholesale, at worst, as just additional government propaganda. The solution may be greater separation. Science should retain its typical conservative (in the non-political sense) approach and disclaim public policy action when the science upon which the policy is relying for its authority, doesn't support that policy. We have good science supporting bad policy, and when the policy fails or backfires, the public will (and has) link the failure with the science, and this may be unjustified if the science didn't support the policy action in the first place...so scientists should say so...beforehand!

I have serious reservations about the conventional presentation of current climate change science. I have to do several gut-checks each time I confront it to try and evaluate if my own biases can be justified. Perhaps I'm wrong, but I think they can, yet I will listen. But I am also tired of being labelled a "denialist" just for having my doubts, and being able to conceive of a mechanism whereupon the science process could be hijacked for a political result. This chapter doesn't soothe this ache any, but instead left me with an impression along the lines of: "You shouldn't take my word for it, but if in fact you don't, you're a denialist because Al Gore got it mostly right. Just sayin'..." Oh man.

Not addressed in Chapter 6 were issues like the co-opting of science for political ends. And climate science could be the poster child for this. We could say that the IPCC's pronouncements that current global warming is human caused are true. Our national and supernational governments immediately leap to a conclusion that they now have license to take action, and that they also know the appropriate action to take and the proper way to assess and balance the consequences of any such action. We've been presented truckloads of new proposals or in some instances been saddled with new law and regulation about various forms of anti-carbon or carbon-trading tax schemes. Evaluations of the likely impact of such schemes all so far as I am aware, all suggest that these will ultimately have insignificant effect, but do significant economic damage in the meanwhile, and simultaneously bolster and centralize government authority over economic affairs. Whoops! Was that what we wanted? The science may be sound, and careful analysis should answer any skepticism in time, but what we really ought to be skeptical of are governments and their plans to fix things. The track record is terrible, and the incentives almost always line up in ways that are destructive to long term freedom, prosperity, and enjoyment of life.

Few realize or take the time to contemplate the implications that the IPCC is primarily a government-consensus body, not a union of concern scientists. Further, it's divided into two groups, Working Group 1, which is charged with public relations, advocacy, and public policy, and whose work is usually what is reported by media. The other is Working Group 2, which in my opinion is the group to actually focus your attention, for this group is more interested in doing the research and integrating the scientific picture.

The results of present science and their interpretation between the two working groups, to my present understanding, has a wide gulf. While WG1 tells you we're sure what's going on here, it's going to be terribly catastrophic for all life on earth, especially human, and the fast majority (>90%) of scientists agree, WG2 is far more conservative, restricting itself to a more reserved opinion that the climate is changing, and that humans are influencing that change, but how bad it could be, and how it might go anyway if humans had no role is not clear. WG2 is more open about its confidence in current understanding of the mechanisms behind the climate system, and shows that the agreement among scientists is not so uniform as WG1 would like you to think; that the basis and confidence for selecting any particular sort of mitigation strategy is very premature at present.

WG2 shows that this science is largely one of measuring and modelling, making ever more complex data models to fit the observed historical data, then extrapolating these models to attempt to forecast the future. But why would such a model work? Answering this key question requires actually understanding the climate system, and unfortunately the focus has been too much on the data modelling (it's easier and gets funding). Here's a lesson on what that can get you:

Ptolemy had presumed the orbits of the planets were circular, and made predictions for their motion that soon strayed from observation. Not wishing to abandon the idea of circular orbits, he was able to introduce increasingly complex modelling terms he called "epicycles" that permitted this original concept to approach any desired level of accuracy and permit the observations to match his model. Great! At least you'll be able to predict where in the sky to look for a planet at any arbitrary time, but holding onto the Ptolemaic model, no matter how precise, would deprive you of actually understanding what was really going on: the planets' orbits are elliptical, not circular, and the reason is gravity. If you don't know this, you cannot progress in understanding the solar system or motion itself. Ptolemy's epicycles would've sufficed to predict the map of the solar system on the sky, but if we had held to them, we would have become stuck in his era, and our modern world would likely look more like his did then, and less like ours does today.

Our climate science is very possibly "Ptolemaic" at this point. And disagreeing with or remaining justifiably skeptical of the IPCC's orthodoxy gets you shunned as a "denialist." I think using such labels at this point is more a way to foreclose legitimate dissent, give license to policy ends for political reasons, and perhaps safeguard government funding streams to certain corners of the science establishment.

Okay, I shall end this massive digression and this review with a nod to Chapter 5, which is very useful if you are a "denialist" because you'll need to consider the sources that are feeding your "denialism". A process of re-normalization and filtering may need to be applied if there is any hope at screening out bias which may be present in opposition arguments. Ultimately, this could require you to become expert in the subject yourself. The end of the book, cited at the top of this writeup, is most helpful in giving you a strategy to proceed short of making that great leap to becoming expert.
Profile Image for Roy.
414 reviews29 followers
February 28, 2021
This is among the best, most careful, writing I've read on the demarcation problem: how to tell if something is "science" versus "not science", and why should we respect the parts that are "science" any more than any other approach to knowledge. It is a sophisticated treatment by a biologist-turned-philosopher, who proves also to be a very skilled writer. This is the kind of book I finish thinking "I'm glad someone wrote this." This really brought together a number of areas relevant to the question of how to think about scientific knowledge and scientific experts, in a single book, and builds a reasonable synthesis out of scientific practice, philosophy of science, epistemology, the role of expertise in society, and the connection of science and society.

I'm likely to assign this book as an additional reading in my class on Science and U.S. Public Policy. It's that good. I'm not sure Pigliucci has said something I didn't know about science in society, but he has said it very well.

The book has three parts. The first is the best, I think, discussing the demarcation problem directly. He talks about science as it is done (and how those who study science have thought about it), about topics on the "borderlands of science" that don't fit but might someday, and about pseudoscience. It's a careful discussion that should provide good insights to anyone just coming to the demarcation problem, or seeking to answer someone who asks why anti-vaxers aren't just as worthy of attention as trained science researchers.

The second part is a good discussion on why such issues seem more controversial today, and discusses the changing media, and the changing roles of public intellectuals in the modern world. This is supplemented by a good survey of the history of science, addressing both how it evolved to the modern approach and how that evolution represents progress. In the course of this, he does a good job of refuting some of the questions about "well if science keeps changing it's mind about how the world works, why should we pay it any attention?"

Finally, in the last large section of the book, he discusses the post-modern critiques of science in detail, in chapters that both show what can be learned from them while also giving clear responses to the most extreme positions. This seems to me a fair discussion, even as he recognizes that scientists, the public, and policymakers usually don't concern themselves with these philosophical questions about science. The public controversies about science, and the role of science as a basis of policy, are driven more by a clash of values and an overly simplistic approach to what science is, as discussed in the previous chapters.

He ends with two chapters where he attempts a synthesis of what he's covered -- difficult but worthwhile -- and a section on how to judge expertise when someone is offering an expert opinion. The later feels a little like an appendix, until he draws it together into his synthesis in the last few pages.

This book is worth reading in its entirety if you are intrigued (or confused) by debates about the role of science in the modern world. It enlightens debates like the recent (2020) debates about whether 'the best science is governing our policy' on the COVID-19 pandemic, even though this book was written before COVID-19. I think this book is likely to stay on my shelf for a long time.
Profile Image for Elliott Bignell.
319 reviews32 followers
March 28, 2023
The subtitle of this book is "How to Tell Science from Bunk". The conclusion basically comes down to "with difficulty". This seems a bit frustrating, in fact it verges on a counsel of despair, but by this point I am not really surprised. Pigliucci is attacking a problem to which he'd obviously like a facile answer just as much as the rest of us, but doing so with real intellectual integrity. It can be hard to take when your allies refrain from carpet-bombing you enemies merely because of some silly concern with integrity, but that seems to make the author a better man than I!

He looks at a whole spectrum of fruitloopery, and there's the rub. Because it really is a spectrum. Are astrology, AW-Denial or creationism pseudo-scientific bunk? Well, obviously. Are thermodynamics or evolution? Obviously not. Are string theory or cold fusion? Er.

The demarcation, to use Popper's term for the problem, is not really clear. Cold fusion might merely be a respectable, speculative experiment that produced a spurious result. Pusztai's experiments with rats and GM food, which I add myself, might be an equally good example. A spurious result is not bunk, it's just the natural course of things. When belief in it persists and waves off repeated failures to replicate the result, on the other hand, you're accelerating off towards the astrology end of the spectrum.

Pigliucci looks into the demarcation problem, some analyses of clear sciences and pseudosciences, and the treatment of science in media and the courts. He looks into intellectualism and the role of intellectuals in public life, including the epidemic of think-tankery which has replaced real intellectual discourse with rent-an-advocate businesses, the peculiarly US culture wars now seeping insidiously across the Atlantic, and the nature of expertise. There are erudite passages on the philosophical history of epistemology and the search for "real" science. He is always fair, sometimes to the point of a deformity and to people to whom I would not have extended the courtesy. He is so excessively fair, in fact, as to criticise Dawkins for his counter-attack on religion, which to me seems to be taking fairness too far. This taboo must fall!

I found the writing a little hard-going at times. Always interesting, but not often lively, and by now I have read so many books around this area that there were few real surprises. One useful nugget was that the thoroughly unpleasant-sounding Newton's quip about standing on the shoulders of giants apparently had less to do with modesty - a quality that Newton can hardly have valued - than with the diminutive stature of his detractor Hooke. There are examples of the catastrophic and sometimes downright silly ways in which scientists have erred, and an uncharacteristically vicious demolition of the lunacies of post-modernism and Feyerabend's fundamentalist relativism.

Frustratingly, the book's final advice is identical to the excuse so often given by AW-Deniers - to learn about the issues and make up your own mind - exactly what lets so much claptrap get through in the first place. However, Pigliucci genuinely seems to have ruled out the alternatives. There's no way to be sure that an expert opinion is really expert without acquainting yourself with the field sufficient to evaluate the plausibility of the claims, and even if you know you have an expert on your hands, they still tend to get it wrong and you need to find enough experts to look for a consensus. "For every expert there is an equal and opposite expert." There's no way around doing the work to get this far.

No litmus test!
Profile Image for Roger.
Author 4 books3 followers
February 28, 2011
He starts by saying he can discard Karl Popper because Popper is too simplistic. But when he wants to show that something is definitely science or definitely not he uses Popper's criteria of falsifiability.
I think there's a misunderstanding of what Popper actually said. Popper was keen to say that for a theory to be scientific it had to be falsifiable, ie there had to be a test we could conceive of (if not actually perform) which, if it turned out a particular way would show the theory was false, or at least inadequate. Pigliucci seems to think Popper was trying to define all science from start to finish. IIRC that is not what Popper was trying to do.

However the bulk of the book is a really good mix of history of science (Galileo, Kepler), philosophy (Aristotle, Hume, Kant, Popper) and the writer tells it well. He also mixes in more recent issues like evolution vs intelligent design arguments and arguments about global warming. It is truly amazing just how much nonsense (on stilts or otherwise) there is out there. He notes that when a theory is actually falsified and then people continue to 'believe' in it, they are not doing science. It seems cold fusion still has adherents.

He does an nice job of separating out the different kinds of science, noting the differences between physics (which generally relay on direct measurements) and the rest. Most other sciences have to resort to interpreting statistical and historical data. Actually this might not be quite so true of quantum physics, but it is a useful analysis.

Finally he looks at how to identify an expert you can trust. Good advice, though somewhat difficult to put in place consistently. But he quotes some bizarre ideas from Post Modernist philosophy (with which he disagrees). Again, it is amazing how much nonsense there is.

So, if you're looking for a solid way to decide if something is science or not go back to Popper. But this is still an excellent read.
Profile Image for Ross Blocher.
480 reviews1,423 followers
September 6, 2022
Nonsense on Stilts is a thorough and careful examination of what science is... and is not. The title comes from philosopher Jeremy Bentham (critiquing the concept of natural rights), but author Massimo Pigliucci uses the phrase here to signify a "really, really tall order of nonsense". And let's face it: there's plenty of obvious nonsense all around us. Pigliucci, a philosopher by trade, isn't taking the easy road, though. He wants to dissect exactly what separates science from pseudoscience (the so-called "demarcation problem"), and to explore the grey areas in between.

There are lots of good answers here for the common, casual dismissals of science. "Scientists get things wrong all the time." "Some things just aren't replicable/falsifiable, so science has nothing to say about them." "Only the hard sciences produce reliable results." Pigliucci also takes on more sophisticated, nuanced questions. "There's a serious replication problem." "Science is a human endeavor, and suffers from all the weaknesses and biases of scientists."

Most of us can point to obvious examples of pseudoscience, such as Creationism or vaccine denialism. Pigliucci has plenty to share about the history of these ideas, and examples of when they have bled into the world and practice of science. He is even more interested in the edge cases, rigorous examinations undertaken by more serious intellectuals, in which falsifiability is hard to establish (evolutionary psychology, string theory) experimental confirmation may be beyond our tools or ability (string theory, SETI - the Search for ExtraTerrestrial Intelligence), or whose motives appear suspect at best (sociobiological theories on race and gender).

Pigliucci also devotes chapters to the influence of media on popular beliefs, the role that science ought to play in society, as well as the rise of think tanks and how they have supplanted the position of public intellectual to give us something far more biased and paid-for. Plus, it wouldn't be a Massimo Pigliucci book if he didn't lead us on a tour of historical philosophers and what they had to say about epistemology and living the best life.

There's so much good observation here (I highlighted many passages for later reference), but it's buried in a lot of overly careful, overly precise language that would prevent me from recommending it to the average reader. Even in my skeptics book club (presumably the target audience), the majority said that it was overly dense, and wondered who this book was for. If you're someone (like me) who reads a lot about science and pseudoscience, this is a valuable book with nuanced arguments, but it's not the book to hand to your crazy uncle Mike who believes lizard people are running the government.
Profile Image for C. Varn.
Author 3 books321 followers
February 3, 2021
A great and fair guide to the spectrum of pseudo-science

Pigliucci 's work on the philosophy of science is solid. The spectrum of difficulties is dealt with more rigorously than it often is in semi I popular treatments of the philosophy science.
Profile Image for Frank Jude.
Author 3 books48 followers
June 12, 2014
The title of Massimo Pigliucci's wonderful, interesting and engaging book says it all: "How To Tell Science From Bunk." As Philip Plait of the Bad Astronomy blog points out, "A frightening percentage of the American population cannot tell the difference between sense and nonsense" and I'd add that this serves the dominant political structures just fine, thank you.

Primarily, Nonsense on Stilts offers an analysis of what has been called "the demarcation problem" which is how to distinguish between science and pseudo-science. The right-wing in American politics is awash in science denialism based upon an almost willful ignore-ance, but there are factions of the left-wing equally vulnerable to pseudo-science (anti-vaxxers as an example of the most egregious, perhaps), and in this book Pigliucci doesn't take sides, but shoots down the logical fallacies and cognitive biases of both camps.

He does this while also offering a penetrating critique of "scientism" while providing a history of the philosophy of science from the ancient Greeks through the overly simplistic analysis of Karl Popper up to a very helpful chapter on how to (probabilistically) decide which "expert" to trust. As well, he quite humorously decimates the nonsense of extreme "post-modernism" whose anti-intellectual, anti-rational relativism has led to devastating effects that are still reeking harm in academia and popular culture. Along the way he spotlights the pseudo-science of "Intelligent Design," H.I.V. and Climate Change denialism.

The chapter titles may help give you a sense of how even-handed Pigliucci is in this valuable text:

Intro: Science versus Pseudoscience and the "Demarcation Problem"
Chap 1: Hard Science, Soft Science
Chap 2: Almost Science
Chap 3: Pseudoscience
Chap 4: Blame the Media?
Chap 5: Debates on Science: The Rise of Think Tanks and the Decline of Public Intellectuals
Chap 6: Science and Politics: The Case of Global Warming
Chap 7: Science in the Courtroom: The Case Against Intelligent Design
Chap 8: From Superstition to Natural Philosophy
Chap 9: From Natural Philosophy to Modern Science
Chap 10: The Science Wars I: Do We Trust Science Too Much?
Chap 11: The Science Wars II: Do We Trust Science Too Little?
Chap 12: Who's Your Expert?
Conclusion: So, What Is Science, After All?
Profile Image for Jim Razinha.
1,379 reviews74 followers
August 27, 2015
With respect to the subtitle of how to tell science from bunk, Pigliucci sadly fails to make his case. Sure, there are extensive side trips into differentiation between examples of science and pseudoscience (i.e., evolution vs creationism/ID), but only to illustrate a very specific point rather than a general approach, and he really doesn't address the "how" - for the most part he merely contrasts and states one is science and the other is not. Too easy for proponents of bunk to pick apart (and too easy for proponents of intelligent reason and science to pick apart.)

There is one rambling chapter on logic, philosophy, and the history of science that does nothing to achieve the subtitle. Description of inductive vs deductive schools of thought (a waste of a chapter focusing on philosophical BS) without application is rather silly. This is not to say that Pigluicci is not right, rather, the knowledge conveyed is useless.

A common theme, he offers no real tools to apply to generic instances. This is a collection of sometimes interesting, if verbose, observations about specific contrasts. And a standard pattern of this book is a disjointed soft segue into something purportedly connected to the preceding chapter, followed by an Emeril-ish BAM! of a not quite sequitur sidebar.

One of the better questions posed was whether one needed to be an expert in both science and pseudoscience to be able to tell the difference, but as per the previous chapters, Pigliucci quickly diverged to explaining what constituted an "expert" rather than answer the question. While claiming to provide a way to tell science from bunk in the last chapter, he actually is giving a way to tell bunk "experts" from possible scientific experts. That has value. But not how he thinks.

Mostly unsatisfying, and sadly so. But he gets an extra star for skewering and roasting Deepak Chopra. That was fun. If short.
Profile Image for John Michael Strubhart.
524 reviews11 followers
September 20, 2011
Massimo Pigliucci has done a fine service for science, science education and the general public in writing this book. While the philosophy does get technical at times, it is well worth the effort of the reader to work his or her way through it. A large portion of our economy, practically all of our health care, much of our military defense, all of our energy consumption, and a good deal of our government's policy comes from or is informed by science. How does a non-scientist tell the difference between what is science an what is bunk? Massimo Pigliucci prepares the read to do so as well as anyone can. In my opinion, this is the most important publication in the field since Carl Sagan's The Demon Haunted World. Highly recommended!

Note: I read the Kindle edition and I was sorely disappointed with the formatting. The publishers did a poor job and a reformatted second edition is badly needed.
Profile Image for Sarah Clement.
Author 1 book114 followers
November 6, 2012
This book reminded me of a lot of philosophy that I had learned and subsequently forgot, but I was grateful for the refresher. I thought he started strong by examining Popper's claim that the defining characteristic of science is falsification, and I liked the first few chapters that explored the boundary of scientist. From here I thought it meandered a bit from the intended purpose of the book, i.e. how to distinguish pseudoscience from science, but the meandering were quite enjoyable as well. I absolutely loved the chapter on postmodernism, though I thought he was quite tempered. He could have said a lot more about the many claims of postmodernism, and its complete lack of utility in helping us understand the world. I understand that not everyone finds postmodernism so interesting, but it really has somehow become deeply imbedded in some corners of academia, which I think makes the critique of this position so important. I thought the last two chapters brought the book back to its original intention, although I actually think Pigliucci undersold our ability to use logic to evaluate knowledge claims and "theories" outside our expertise. Sure, it can be difficult if we know nothing about it, and he makes the point that some arguments are so patently ridiculous that we can dismiss them outright. But I think that we can still use reason to help us evaluate the claims of various experts, and we don't need to so readily resort to evaluating the experts as he suggests. I also think his framework for evaluating expertise could be rather difficult to implement in practice, and would still take more time than many people would be willing to commit to.

One more thing - since I picked on Chris Mooney for his parenthesis, I have to say....Pigliucci is in love with parentheticals. They are all over the book, and they can get quite distracting.
Profile Image for Terry.
507 reviews20 followers
June 24, 2010
Organization: The chapters did not flow in any reasonable sense as it pertained to the topic of the book. There were sections in the center where he attacks Bjorn Lambourg, the Postmodernists, as well as includes a history of scientific thinking. While these were enjoyable, all except the attacks on the postmodernists didn't exactly fit the progression that the author was making. The last two chapters should have been pushed up considerably as the expert problem and checklist of what makes a science should have come shortly after the introduction.

Writing: Massimo is a master of concise prose and uses analogies that advance the point at hand. His mastery of what others have said gives him access to wonderful ways to summarize ideas and distill important points quickly; other authors could wind up using twice as many words to say the same thing without adding anything.

Notes: Some of the footnotes were both funny and illuminating. I very much wish they'd been the bottom-of-the-page kind rather than the all-lumped-at-the-end kind.

Topics: The selection of targets was well done and got at issues that other books seemed to skip like how to gauge expertise and how Bayesianism and Prospectivism can be used to both support the efficacy of science and recognize the problem of qualia.
Profile Image for Bill.
35 reviews
March 12, 2014
Started off OK but eventually turned into a seemingly endless diatribe focusing on the topics of global warming and evolution. And for a book that is supposed to be sticking to facts and science the author couldn't help himself and brings politics into the discussion again and again with an overwhelming bias in one direction. It all could have been covered a lot faster and with less rambling on if he could have stuck to the facts, limited the analogies (many of which were just as ill placed as the kind he bashed when used by others that didn't fall into line with his own beliefs and biases) and not veered towards attacks on specific people or groups of people. I fall in the middle politically so disagree very little with the ultimate conclusions on each topic covered but found much of the book frustrating to listen to. Finding an editor to help limit the overuse of certain words and phrases, especially the word MOREOVER, would have helped make this a better listen.
Profile Image for Katie.
117 reviews1 follower
June 23, 2019
His writing tone is arrogant and mocking of others, especially religious people. He keeps saying that "being religious is fine just don't claim creationism is science" but continues to compare believing in a deity to believing in magic (he compares praying for healing to going to a magician instead of a doctor in one of the chapters on the so-called "science wars"). Let's put it this way: the second edition of this book includes an added chapter on "scientism" and "virtue epistemologies" which me and my fellow science PhD students found funny because it was both ironic and hypocritical. Long story short: the content was fine, the tone of the author was offensive - especially to many of the international students in the class. The creationism=science thing is kind of an American phenomenon and my fellow students from other countries were baffled by the assumption that one cannot both believe in God and believe in science (inc. evolution) and so found this book distasteful.
12 reviews
November 27, 2011
Chapters one and two offer some useful examination of what practicing science means, allowing for both the hard and soft sciences, while highlighting what characteristics make some examples "almost science". The rest of the book read as an increasingly tiring complaint about how various people's views about science are wrong, and a brief historical survey of Important Science People that got sidetracked in distracting ways. Much of the book was spent in telling the reader what they just read, what they will get to if they keep reading, and that this or that topic is out of scope for the book, so won't be covered, leaving me feeling I hadn't actually learned anything from this rambling survey.
Profile Image for Brian Croup.
68 reviews
August 7, 2012
Seems like Massimo Pigliucci felt the need to use this book to preach his own view on a number of scientific issues. Would have preferred a more analytical and scientific presentation of the difference between "Science and Bunk".
Profile Image for Clifford.
14 reviews4 followers
February 12, 2014
It was hard to finish this book when the author does not even follow his own advice for determination of bunk versus science and elevates unproven theories declaring them as absolute fact.
Profile Image for David Dinaburg.
296 reviews49 followers
December 28, 2013
When I start writing a review for Goodreads, I take current personal activities or events and wrap them around the major concepts I draw from the recently finished book. Since it is the end of the year, there isn’t much going on; it’s not a simple thing to connect the labyrinthine negotiations of Giantbomb’s Game of Year deliberations, nor the sudden forced acknowledgement of middle age—thrust upon me by carrying both a close friend’s baby at our annual hometown reunion and my grandmother in and out of a nursing home—to a book about the fundamental prescriptions surrounding a working definition of science. Nonsense on Stilts: How to Tell Science from Bunk is a silhouette portrait, tackling head-on what I learned from the book itself is known as “the demarcation problem” of science.

I found the strap a bit misleading; enclosed is not primarily a harangue against pseudoscience and bunk, nor a how-to manual of distinguishment between scientific processes and charlatanism—How to Tell Science from Bunk could easily be truncated to How to Tell Science. No, it is closer to a treatise on the general shape and size of science, focusing on the negative space left when you cut out what clearly isn’t science from what certainly is:
Popper and falsification are representative of a somewhat prescriptive steak in philosophy of science, that is, of a tradition of philosophers actually telling scientists how they ought to carry out their work. As we have seen, Popper was motivated by the so-called demarcation problem--the difficulty in distinguishing science from non- and pseudoscience--the very issue that is central to this book. He was also bothered by Hume’s problem of induction, and yet the only reason we have to trust induction is because it worked in the past (which is itself a form of induction, making the whole thing perilously close to being circular).
Being shown the still-unanswered seams in Science is far more elucidating than simply digging into the endless streams of hacks and fakers. Showing the reader how to circumscribe Science themselves, rather than claiming by PhD-fiat that “this is notscience because scientists say so,” is, to use a colloquial and ironically pious idiom, practicing what you preach.

The schadenfreude of watching a learned scholar tear into absolute nonsense masquerading as provable hypotheses was, if I’m being perfectly honest, a large reason why I picked up Nonsense on Stilts. I already liked Massimo Pigliucci from his appearances on The Skeptic’s Guide to the Universe, so I entered the book with confirmation bias blazing. I wasn’t disappointed that Nonsense on Stilts wasn’t simply a parade of horribles or a series of pseudoscientific strawmen to knock down—actual insights and serious discussions about how to define science were both interesting and welcome. Having personally not heard of the above-mentioned “Demarcation Problem” or Popper’s work therein, nor dwelt upon the underlying assumptions that prop up scientific theory at its core, Nonsense worked for me as a primer for the why more than the how of Science:
Scientific practice requires the assumption of naturalism, that is, the idea that natural phenomena are, well, natural, and therefore scientists do not need to invoke the supernatural to explain them. In fact, we noted that scientists themselves invoke naturalism as a postulate of science whenever they need to make the (convincing) argument that the so-called theory of intelligent design is not science because of its supernatural basis. The important thing to realize is that in the context of our discussion naturalism is not an empirically verifiable position, and it is therefore by definition outside of science itself. If science is about anything at all, it is about empirically verifiable statements concerning the world.
Thinking about science in terms of broad philosophy comes more naturally for me, personally, than ritualistic employment of formulae. In fact, the few times I deviated from Nonsense was when the author took to task some of the more literary interpretations of theoretical physics:
Now here is a comment, quoted by Sokal, that Latour made on Einstein’s theory of relativity, in which he takes to task “[Einstein’s] obsession with transporting information through transformation without deformation; his passion for the precise superimposition of readings; his panic at the idea that observers sent away might betray, might retain privileges, and send reports that could not be used to expand our knowledge; his desire to discipline the delegated observers and to turn them into dependent pieces of apparatus that do nothing but watch the coincidence of hands and notches.” This would be comical if it weren’t such a sad example of the misunderstanding of science by a nonscientist. First of all, Latour is criticizing a popular book by Einstein, not a technical article, presumably because Latour simply cannot understand a technical paper in fundamental physics (full disclosure: nor can I, nor most people living on the planet—but some of us try not to write commentaries about things we do not understand). More importantly, Einstein was explaining his theory through a thought experiment, using hypothetical human observers to help describe the nuances of the concept. Latour’s talk of “panic,” “betrayal,” and “privileges” is complete emotive nonsense. This is physics, not a Shakespearian tragedy.
If Einstein’s thought experiment of using hypothetical human observers was simply a tool to allow interpretation of a nuanced technical concept that was beyond the ken of most readers, then surely Latour positing human emotionality upon the hypothetical figures is not nearly so absurd? Surely Latour isn’t saying that the key component of Einstein’s theory is that of near-human automatons that do nothing but check watches and report maths. Rather, it can be understood as a literary critique of a popular exemplar of scientific writing, wherein the human element is cordoned off from the theoretical processes—where people are excluded from a perfect experimental vacuum. The “emotive nonsense” is simply a way to “help describe the nuances of the concept”; I believe the concept being explored is not physics, but the interpretation of literature outside of the prescripts of fictive writing; applying theoretical (literary) structure to functional (scientific) text. Not a commentary on physics, but on literature and reader interpretation, asking the question of why we can create the hypothetical clock-watchers, who are as “real” as Shakespeare’s King Lear, but relegate them to functional timekeepers without a “life” of their own. All are vehicles, constructed by words on a page, for delivery of nuance—scientific theory too opaque for most. Why accept the benefits of use of people as timepieces and then mock the sublimation of personality upon them?


Nonsense on Stilts focused more on the philosophy of science than I expected, and outside of the soft jeering at a somewhat strained literary reinterpretation of mathematical word problems, I appreciated what it opened up for me. That is not to say I didn’t get some good, old-fashioned pseudoscience debunking, particularly the methodical dismemberment of Astrology:
Physicists recognize three more forces in nature (other than gravity): the strong and weak nuclear interactions, and electromagnetism. That’s it--there are no other known physical forces to play with. We can exclude the strong and weak nuclear forces, because they can only be effective at the scale of atomic or subatomic, not astronomical, distances. Electromagnetism is a more promising candidate, but only at first glance. Again, this is something that science has studied for a long time, and we can measure the electromagnetic fields of the various planets and of the sun. Turns out that the latter is the only one that has any significant effect, as can be seen every time that there is a solar magnetic storm, a phenomenon capable of interfering with our communications and in some cases even causing blackouts in major cities. But if electromagnetism is the conduit of the astral influences than astrology should be based just on the sun--forget the moon, planet, and other stars. Clearly, that is not compatible with astrological practice.

It is always possible for the astrologer to retreat one step further and claim that astral influences are mediated by a fifth, yet undiscovered force. We cannot be certain that there is no such thing as a fifth force, but everything that has happened in theoretical and experimental physics over the past century indicates that there are only four fundamental forces...moreover, even if there were a fifth force, it would appear logical to assume that—like every force known so far—its action too depends on distance, meaning that the further away two objects are the less strength force X will have. If this is the case, then astrologers would still not be out of the woods, because they insist on treating all planets as having the same influence on human affairs, regardless of distance. This means that not only do they have to assume the existence of a fifth force, which is improbable enough, but also that this would be the only force whose action does not decrease with distance, thereby piling improbability upon improbability.
Also tackled were the three dimensional nature of space impacting constellational formations, the shifting of the coordinates of the night sky over the past millennia, the recent discover of millions of “new” stars that should entangle the ancient star charts, and so on. It was fun, and it helps to shore up the distinction between science and nonscience.

As I stated at the top, I bring whatever else I’m preoccupied with into the writing of these reviews. The colloquialism about watching how the sausage is made is a graphic shortcut to remind people that the functional processes leading up to a finished product is at least partially grotesque and unappealing to most people. If you’ll indulge me, it’s why Game of the Year awards (or, Academy Awards for less videogame-centric people) are presented and the behind-the-scenes footage is either fully obscured or only available to true fanatics. GiantBomb, my prior example, records and publishes their discussions—ten or so hours of deliberations—that would be incredibly boring to most people but are snapped up eagerly by their acolytes. It is hard to imagine the tedium of listening to six people you’d never heard of talk about things you don’t care about—you need to know about Brad, Jeff and Vinny et al to care about their tastes, and need to know the year in video games to understand their discussions about the best of 2013. Esotericism amongst the esoteric. But if you do care, then there is something both appealing and grotesque about watching the process behind the finished product—in this case, the grinding processes behind the slick presentation of the game of the year lists.

Why do we care about media awards when discussing a book about science? Well, science is all process. You don’t get the finished product unless you dig through the hundreds of years of prior fits and starts. And those deliberations never end, because that’s all the scientific process is:
It is certainly true that “Darwin’s theory is a theory,” in the same way that it is true that my chair is a chair, that is, by definition (notice, incidentally, that just like modern mechanical physics is not “Newton’s theory,” the modern theory of evolution is not “Darwin’s theory,” but a more advanced and sophisticated theory known as the Modern Synthesis). Second, the theory is not a fact, again, by definition. Scientific theories are just what the board states they are: explanations meant to unify a broad range of observations. Facts are observations that the theory attempts to make sense of, which is why the standard creationist refrain that “evolution is a theory, not a fact” is at the same time (almost) correct and yet entirely irrelevant. Moreover, the business about gaps in the theory “for which there is not evidence” betrays a profound misunderstanding of the nature of scientific theories: every theory has “gaps,” meaning sets of facts that are not (currently) explained by the theory, or conversely, makes hypothetical statements that are not (currently) supported by empirical evidence. This is true for evolution, quantum mechanics, general relativity, or whatever. Theories are human constructs meant to guide our understanding of nature, and as such have always been and will always be “incomplete.” Once one realizes that this is a normal condition of science, it will not come as a surprise that the theory of evolution has “gaps.”
If you introduce someone to, say, Giantbomb.com via their Game of the Year deliberations, you’re not likely to create an avid video game fan, because it’s hard to care about the process until you know something about the subject. Why is anyone surprised that it is little different from being thrust into school setting where you’re taught force equals mass times acceleration? It’s sort of like hearing Brad thinks Brothers is one of the best games of 2013; meaningless without context.
Perhaps the most elegant and devastating critique of the Aristotelian conception of physics was made by Galileo through a thought experiment[citation omitted]: Aristotle had claimed that bodies fall at a speed that depends on their weight, the heavier bodies faster than the lighter ones. Galileo therefore invited his readers to consider a situation in which a heavier and a lighter body were joined by a cord and were falling together. According to Aristotelian physics, the heavier one should drag the lighter one down faster so that the combined body would have a higher speed than the lighter by itself. Then again, by the same Aristotelian theory, the lighter body would be expected to slow down the heavier one, so that the combined bodies would fall at a slower speed than the heavy body by itself. The punchline is that the first prediction is logically contradictory to the second one: one cannot be true without the other one being false, and yet Aristotle would have to admit that both stem out of his conception of bodies and speed. Ergo, Aristotle’s conception of bodies and speed must be wrong. One can imagine the ancient Greek nodding approvingly at the genius of the Italian scientist and admitting defeat. Although common lore wants it that Galileo, being a good scientist, actually performed the experiment by dropping different weights from the tower in Pisa, there is much historical doubt that he actually did.
I learned of the weight-drop experiment, but never was it put into context of refuting Aristotle; simply presented as a foundational block of how the world works. I don’t have an answer for finding an entry point into the whole of science, just like I wouldn’t know how to direct people into enjoying video game discussions, outside of “play more games.” “Do more science,” I suppose, must suffice.

As I revealed at the beginning of this review, and have mentioned time and again throughout this review, I typically endeavor to tie in whatever I’m doing or seeing with whatever I just read. Sometimes it works. Sometimes it doesn’t. Whether or not you care about my process that leads to my particular finished review, Nonsense on Stilts will, for a time anyway, make you aware that the grinding is as important as the sausage.
Profile Image for Kike Ramos.
220 reviews33 followers
February 3, 2019
English / Español

In this book, the author presents us with an argument for the importance to distinguish between science, quasi-science and pseudoscience, given the importance of this topic in today's society.

For once, I think the argument is really compelling, and he pulls it off while recognizing science as a human activity with its own flaws. I agree that this subject is important, specially as a psychologist who faces pseudoscientific arguments on my field every day.

I recommend this to anyone interested in science or someone who wants to learn how to recognize BS.

______

Español

En este libro el autor argumenta sobre la importancia de distinguir entre lo que es ciencia, quasi-ciencia y pseudociencia, dada la importancia de este tema en nuestra sociedad actual.

El argumento me convence bastante y es presentado al mismo tiempo que se reconoce a la ciencia como una actividad humana imperfecta. Concuerdo con la idea de que este tema es de vital importancia, sobre todo porque soy un psicólogo que se enfrenta a argumentos y posturas pseudocientíficas constantemente.

Lo recomiendo para cualquiera que esté interesado en la ciencia o cualquiera que desee aprender a diferenciar entre la ciencia y cualquier otra tontería.
Profile Image for Robert Wechsler.
Author 13 books131 followers
March 28, 2023
This book goes well beyond its subtitle (and is far from a how-to book, although there is some helpful advice), but fortunately I was interested in all the related topics the author discusses. and I found his voice intelligent and believable. The other topics include pseudoscience and quasi-science, hard and soft science, the history of science, scientism, expertise, and media coverage of science.

Anyone who cites logical fallacies is my kind of person, but Pigliucci does sometimes select authors and quotes that make his task too easy.
Profile Image for Todd Martin.
Author 4 books77 followers
November 20, 2017
You’d think that as science and technology has progressed that there would be an overall increase in knowledge and a corresponding decrease in nonsensical thinking. Unfortunately, there seems to be more deluded, wishy-washy, pseudo science floating around than ever due in large part to an internet and uncritical news media that gives equal weight to real and imaginary ideas alike. In “Nonsense on Stilts”, Massimo Pigliucci (who has 3 PhD’s in genetics, botany and philosophy of science) attempts to sort throught this overabundance of information to tease out the differences between science, quasi-science, pseudo science, hard science, soft science and non-science (or nonsense).

The book consists of a collection of essays which cover various aspects of the science / pseudoscience debate using topics such as creationism and global warming denialism as illustrative examples.

Because his day job is as a philosopher at the City University of New York, Pigliucci focuses heavily on philosophy as the best means of distinguishing truth from bunk spending several long and rather dull chapters on the history of philosophy and philosophical thought. While philosophy may have it’s place in the discussion, science is a far more powerful tool for unearthing truth and plays a far more important role in society. A quick look around reveals that science continues to make meaningful discoveries which add to the body of human knowledge. Philosophy may inform these discoveries, but plays a far less significant role in human understanding today than it once did.

The book goes downhill from there becoming purely philosphical, at one point even delving into the subject of “qualia” (subjective experience) – perhaps one of the least interesting questions of all time.

So what is science? It’s an endeavor that consists of three components:
1) It is naturalistic (no supernaturalism allowed)
2) It employs theories to provide explanations
3) It is empirically testable.
Profile Image for Tom Schulte.
3,100 reviews68 followers
April 22, 2014
This is basically a history of and paean to the scientific method. I was intrigued by the references to the philosophy of Karl Popper (I must read some of his works) and specifically a deeper exploration of falsibility and his object of the Demarcation Problem, finding where science ends and whatever else there is begins. Whatever is out there beyond science is, basically, nonsense to Pigliucci and he holds forth for extensive attach on Creationism and ID which goes a bit long, I think. His history of paranormal research and specifically the Princeton Engineering Anomalies Research (PEAR) program established at Princeton University is very interesting. I have long wanted to read a history of the eugenics movement, it seems such a fascinating example of crowd delusion, and this work contains an extensive section on this topic.
Profile Image for Russ.
65 reviews7 followers
May 21, 2011
For a non-scientist, this book was a great introduction to the history of the philosophy of science as well as providing tools to help the lay person identify bunk and psudoscience. The book uses the current populuar culture debates in the U.S. about evolution (Hint: Science deals with the natural world. If someone proposes a supernatual explanation for something it isn't science) and global warming as examples on how to identify actual science and recognize when arguments are sponsored or self-serving.

I liked this book quite a lot and recomend it to anyone interested in the above mentioned debates or science in general but I should point out that the reading level of this book raises it above most popular science books. This reads more like a graduate level text book than most of the books you see on the NYT bestseller list. Don't get me wrong, the book was a very enjoyable read, some readers might just find the vocabulary challenging.
Profile Image for Carmel-by-the-Sea.
120 reviews18 followers
January 4, 2020
Niestety.

Ponieważ myślenie nastawione na racjonalizm, krytycyzm, ciekawość świata i wytrwałe poszukiwanie, jest istotą nie tylko uprawiania nauki, ale i bycia odpornym na manipulacje obywatelem, z przykrością muszę stwierdzić, że opiniowana książka nie zmniejszy społecznego deficytu takiego myślenia. "Bujda na resorach. Jak odróżnić naukę od bredni" filozofa nauki, a w szczególności biologii, Massimo Pigliucciego to lektura pełna sprzeczności - poutykanych niejasności, niespójnych wywodów, choć czasem ciekawych spostrzeżeń, które jednak giną w autorskim i translatorskim niechlujstwie. Sporo potencjału na dobrą lekturę książka utraciła przez bijący po oczach kompleks autora. Nie rozumie nauk ścisłych i zakłada ich nieuprawioną ekspansję w rejony, które kiedyś stanowiły domenę filozofii. Główny problem z pseudonauką to nie jest scjentyzm, który pod koniec pracy urósł u Pigliucciego do rangi podstawowej bolączki, ale wszechobecne niezrozumienie w społeczeństwie istoty uprawiania nauki. Oskarżenie wybitnych fizyków i biologów o zapędy scjentystyczne to nieuprawiona i bardzo subiektywna ocena, szczególnie że filozof przepiął im tę łatkę bez uzasadnienia.

Teraz mógłbym ze smutkiem zakończyć opis moich wrażeń, bo w sumie tytuł książki zapowiadał ciekawy tekst. Jednak postaram się kilka tez ze wstępu rozwinąć.

Autor na początku zadeklarował, że pokaże: jak działa nauka, kim jest intelektualista, ekspert, specjalista, gdzie jest granica między nauką a nie-nauką, para-nauką, pseudo-nauką. Zapowiedział, że opisze podstawy historii nauki, skupiając się epistemologii i przykładach błędów w poszukiwaniu prawdy. Następnie zaplanował rozprawienie się z astrologią, telekinezą, postmodernizmem i scjentyzmem, by finalnie połechtać ego czytelnika, że po lekturze będzie sprawniej odróżniał brednie od faktów. Wszystkie z tych rzeczy zrobił, ale większość źle. Był zarówno tendencyjny, jak i nieprzekonujący w dobranych przykładach. Niefrasobliwie tracił atut prowadzenia poważnego wywodu, szczególnie podczas wycieczek osobistych (na przykład w opisach scjentyzmu - str. 335-347). Nie zrozumiał współczesnej wersji falsyfikacji w ramach projektu SETI (str. 73), czego dowiódł opisując dociekania Poppera czy Kuhna (str. 313-319). Falsyfikacja (jeśli już w nauce ktoś tego pojęcia używa) oznacza, że oczekujemy od teorii, modelu czy stawianej tezy, iż da się ją poddać doświadczalnej weryfikacji (co do zasady). Samo pojęcie nauki, które starał się Pigliucci wyartykułować w drugim rozdziale, okaza��o się mętne i mało uchwytne. Zabrakło mi jasnego opisania zestawu zasad metody naukowej. Szkoda analizować poglądy Kartezjusza czy Bacona, by coś pokazać w ich metodzie, lepiej faktycznie precyzyjniej podać reguły obowiązujące teraz, bo nikt (no niemal nikt, ale nie warto zabiegać o względy płaskoziemców) już nie potrzebuje argumentu za kulistością nasze planety, a raczej spójnego i czytelnego opisania jak nauka kumulując fakty i eliminując błędy (metodologiczne, braki obiektywne wynikające z niedoskonałości technikaliów, itd), buduje obraz świata (str. 277).

Plusów jest trochę, ale jak dla mnie, za mało. Sporo miejsca autor poświęcił na społeczny i kulturowy wymiar nauki, szczególnie analizując zagubienie 'zwykłego obywatela' w docierającym do niego przekazie związanym z treściami, wobec których jest laikiem. Filozof nie daje pewnych rad, których obiektywnie nie ma, ale namawia, tu akurat dobranymi dobrze przykładami, do zdrowej zasady, by zawsze dać sobie czas na przeanalizowanie czegoś, co do nas trafia jako informacja czy wiedza; warto zapamiętać przytoczone słowa Carla Sagana: "nie chcesz, by twój umysł był tak otwarty, żeby mógł wypaść twój mózg" (str. 148). Bardzo dobrze opisał Pigliucci etapy formowania się specjalisty, jako człowieka latami budującego w umyśle spójny obraz przedmiotu fachowych dociekań (str. 368-369).

Moje mniej lub bardziej zasadne utyskiwania na język, układ treści czy niekonsekwencje dydaktyczne, stanowią zaledwie dodatek do kilku poważnych zarzutów, które stawiam autorowi "Bujdy na resorach". W kontekście niepełnego podania metody naukowej, przesadne akcentowanie wkładu filozofii nauki (w szczególności epistemologii) do procesu badawczego uważam za typowy grzech filozofów. Wydumane pojęcie 'epistemologia cnót' czyni, według autora, z ludzkiej (subiektywnej i uwikłanej kulturowo) aktywności obiektywny sąd o świecie (str. 350-351). Dla mnie ten wywód jest bzdurny, nielogiczny (wewnętrznie sprzeczny). Przy okazji pokazuje kierunek uroszczeń filozofów wobec nauk szczegółowych - jakby samo pojęcie powoływało do życia wartość, z której naukowcy powinni czerpać. Dla mnie takie konstrukcje to przejaw słabości współczesnej filozofii, ukrytych intencji autora i jego kompleksów. Te ostatnie jaskrawiej widać, gdy kuriozalnie upomina naukowców, że błądzą, bo nie korzystają z ustaleń filozofii (str. 277):

"W kręgach filozoficznych korespondencyjna teorię prawdy w znacznym stopniu zastąpiły bardziej wyrafinowane stanowiska epistemologiczne, chociaż wielu naukowców (i oczywiście duża część społeczeństwa) żyje w błogiej nieświadomości tego faktu. Epistemologia jest dziedziną filozofii zajmującą się tym, jak zdobywamy wiedzę i dzięki temu dochodzimy do prawdy."

Tęsknoty za wielką i tłumaczącą wszystko filozofią, czytelne aż nadto. Do podobnych miraży autor nawiązuje jeszcze kilkukrotnie (w rozdziale o scjentyzmie). Przytaczając poglądy specjalistów, którzy naukowe rozumienie świata stawiają wysoko (zbyt wysoko, według filozofa) - Stevena Weinberga, Sama Harrisa, Stevena Hawkinga, Richarda Dawkinsa, Michaela Shermera czy Neil de Grasse Tysona - wykazuje się wieloma uprzedzeniami (str. 264, 275-276, 335-337) . Ich wyrwane z kontekstu poglądy nie są przedyskutowane, a nawet trudno zrozumieć co przez ich przytoczenie filozof chciał uzyskać. Pozostaje zdziwienie i niesmak. Całości dopełnia pogubienie się w rozumieniu nauki, gdy polemizuje z Harrisem i Shermerem (str. 335-336):

"Podejście obu tych ludzi do nauki o moralności dogłębnie przeanalizowałem, ale, mówiąc krótko, sklasyfikowałem je jako scjentystyczne z racji ich intelektualnego totalitaryzmu: sugerują najwyraźniej nie to, że nauka może WSPOMAGAĆ dyskurs moralny (...), tylko raczej - że podejście naukowe jest JEDYNYM, które może z pożytkiem podjąć się zgłębiania tego tematu. W ten sposób ignoruje się wieki poważnych dokonań naukowych, najwyraźniej na tej podstawie, że są 'nudne' czy 'w sposób oczywisty' nieistotne."

Pomijając trudną do udowodnienia tezę o totalitaryzmie (czego Pigliucci się nawet niepodejmuje, tylko podaje link do własnego artykułu), otwarte jest pytanie - czy 'obaj panowie' uznają naukę za jedyny wartościowy byt, czy jednak jego elementy ignorują?

Bardzo przewrotnym i chyba nieświadomie przeciwskutecznym wydał mi się autor, gdy analizował postawy postmodernistyczne. Z jednej strony trafnie wyśmiał istotę takich poglądów (str. 300-306), ale następnie, opisując koncepcję Longino (str. 320-323, 345), przesadnie skorelował i uwikłał naukę z kulturą. W efekcie, według filozofa, nauka cierpi na wiele nieuchronnych przypadłości, które według mnie są po części wydumane i wyabstrahowane z istniejących istotnych różnic między tzw. naukami 'twardymi' i 'miękkimi' (przy czym o ich wzajemnej ciekawej relacji sam wcześniej pisze interesująco). Ostatecznie, pośrednio, Pigliucci staje się zwolennikiem postmodernizmu.

Nie mogę oszczędzić tłumacza. Jestem niemal pewien, że bardzo skwapliwie korzystał z internetowych tłumaczy, tak bezrefleksyjnie. To widać jednoznacznie w kilku miejscach, szczególnie w ostatnich zdaniach rozdziału drugiego (str. 57). Jak na PWN i zaporową cenę - niemal haniebne niedopatrzenie.

Ponieważ notatek z lektury zrobiłem sporo, a brak na ich analizę miejsca, to by wzmocnić podstawy moich negatywnych odczuć, i może zachęcić innych czytelników do zbudowania własnych opinii, wyliczę hasłowo dość skandaliczne tezy autora:

• Powtarzanie doświadczalne pomiarów wielkości fizyko-chemicznych czasem jest wątpliwe według autora, skoro pojawiają się w nich rozbieżności (str. 55-56)
• Relacja między równaniem Drake'a (o szacowaniu liczby cywilizacji pozaziemskich) i projektem SETI mają zdecydowanie bardziej luźny związek, niż sugeruje autor (str. 81).
• Przykład z błędnym szacunkiem przez Thomsona wieku Słońca (str. 281-282) pokazuje nie wyższość biologii nad fizyką, tylko fakt, że nauka działa zgodnie z aktualnymi teoriami (konsekwencja nieistniejącej wtedy wiedzy o reakcjach jądrowych) i że 'jak walec' rozprawia się ona z pomyłkami, które spotykają nawet najlepszych. Przykład należało ująć w narrację o sile nauki, kumulowaniu faktów i eliminacji błędów w świetle nowych ustaleń.
• Autor nie rozumie istoty paradoksu bliźniąt (str. 303) szczególnej teorii względności (ale nie powstrzymało go to przed jego przytoczeniem).
• Z 'afery Sokala' zrobił filozof studium przypadku, zamiast (zgodnie z intencją Sokala) przykład obnażenie bardzo niepokojącego zjawiska włączania w nauki społeczne pojęć z nauk ścisłych w sposób bezmyślny, choć w mniemaniu autorów takich prac, zgodny z modą i potrzebą, by nadać własnym wywodom powagi i uczoności (str. 356). (*)
• Pigliucci uważa, że logiczne myślenie ma wątpliwe zastosowanie poza matematyką (str. 371).

Podsumowanie.

Dla mnie to świetna lektura do dekonstrukcji, wykazywania niejasności, nieścisłości i dominującej u mnie tym razem krytyki (przez to ocena byłaby wysoka) - tekst idealny do analizy błędów na różnych poziomach - polecam. Ale ostatecznie oceniam całość - jako przekaz do czytelnika - bardzo przeciętnie i raczej nie polecam.

=============

(*) Alan Sokal w 1996 w prestiżowym czasopiśmie 'Social Text' opublikował kompletna bzdurę, zlepek myśli postmodernistów. Cały tekst publikacji i szeroka analiza kontekstu tej prowokacji dostępna jest w "Modnych bzdurach" (Sokal, Bricmont - Prószyński i S-ka 2004)
Modne bzdury. O nadużyciach nauki popełnianych przez postmodernistycznych intelektualistów.
Profile Image for Robert Lewis.
Author 3 books16 followers
October 30, 2019
With a title like "Nonsense on Stilts" and a publisher description promising that the book will "separate fact from fantasy," I initially expected a fairly stereotypical work debunking such topics as astrology, dowsing, and creationism much like some of the works of other authors like James Randi or Michael Shermer. While this book does indeed spend some time explaining what's wrong with astrology and creationism (and both Randi's and Shermer's names make appearances in the text), this is actually a much more serious work in the philosophy of science. Its stated goal is to help the reader solve the "demarcation problem" of identifying the distinctions or borders between science, non-science, and pseudoscience.

While unexpected, the result is a book that is as important as it is timely. The Information Age has given us unprecedented access to novel arguments, facts, and opinions, but our educational institutions and media have largely failed to prepare most people to critically engage with such materials. Worse, even our leading "public intellectuals" often fail to clearly define the boundaries of their expertise or even to identify the qualitative differences between what they consider to be good science and what they consider to be pseudoscience. Pigliucci's book is a valiant attempt to draw the boundaries between science and pseudoscience, not only in terms of the few examples he provides, but in abstract theoretical terms applicable to any other issue or phenomenon.

While I may quibble with specific points of the author's philosophy, I think the book is an overall success, and I admire the care with which the author crafted his points, drawing important distinctions between, say, the "hard" and "soft" sciences or the differences between scientific areas of inquiry (evolutionary biology, for instance) and humanistic fields which may merely be informed by scientific inquiry (evolutionary psychology, for example), all while making it clear that the distinction between these disciplines is an epistemological one with little bearing on the quality of research produced in such fields. The author's treatment of pseudoscience, on the other hand, is (justifiably) much harsher. The reader interested in polemical rants against specific pseudosciences will likely be disappointed, however. While the author doesn't hide his own opinions on such matters (in fact, his tangential asides regarding such matters occasionally distract from the point he's trying to make), they are not the focus of the book. Disappointing as that might be to much of the modern skeptical movement, the result is a much more effective guide to thinking about science.

There are two competing philosophies with which the author takes particular issue: scientism and postmodernism. Both very much deserve the author's criticism and our scorn, though I think he fails to strike the right balance in the tone of his criticism. While both are incorrect philosophical positions, I would argue that postmodernism presents the much larger threat to reasonable scholarship. This book, then, would have benefited had the author dedicated more pages to delivering a more forceful critique of postmodern philosophy (which I would call the very embodiment of "nonsense on stilts") and fewer pages to the scientistic perspective which few practicing scientists actually endorse (despite the author's laundry list of noted scientists and science communicators who have at least flirted with scientism).

That having been said, the only portion of the book that I think actually missed its mark was the sixth chapter concerning public intellectuals and think tanks. While the author's contention that think tanks are ideological organizations dedicated to the perpetuation of their own opinions rather than impartial scientific research is largely correct, his argument that public intellectualism has largely fallen out of favor, replaced by these organizations is unconvincing. Worse, the chapter fails to offer a satisfactory definition of what qualifies one as an intellectual (much less a public intellectual). That's not to say the chapter contains no good points. Rather, my complaint is simply that the chapter's brevity offers insufficient space to fully develop these ideas (the economist Thomas Sowell dedicated an entire book to a similar topic in his "Intellectuals and Society"). Furthermore, the comparison between public intellectuals (whatever they may be) and think tanks devolves rapidly into a list of think tank publications of which the author disapproves rather than (as would have been more productive) analyzing the changing and increasingly-democratized marketplace for intellectual content in the Internet age.

Despite these flaws, on the whole I found this book to be at once accessible and intellectually stimulating. Many people who claim to be either scientists or devotees of the scientific enterprise would benefit greatly from a study of its philosophical treatment of the subject.
Profile Image for Wendelle.
1,747 reviews52 followers
Read
July 29, 2020
This is a timely book to read in the current crisis of information and disinformation. The author, biologist and philosopher Massimo Pigliucci, tackles a wide array of topics regarding the characters of 'science,' 'soft science', 'pseudoscience', and 'anti-science.' These include topics like the different methodologies of science, the different levels of prediction and accountability of 'hard science' and 'soft science', the curiously inverse relationship between the reputation of the 'public intellectual' and the proliferation of dogmatically-driven think tanks, and the prevalence of detrimental media tactics to provide dichotomous scientific and anti-scientific views equal space and hence false equivalence. The book discusses some of the usual suspects such as the manufactured climate science controversies, the well-funded agenda of intelligent design, astrology, modern witch hunts, the history of eugenics, and the science wars stemming from the panic and resentment postmodernists had regarding science.

I especially found the sections where the author analyzes the subjects of SETI and evolutionary psychology and declares that both are not science; this is news to me. The author shows that SETI is a possibly endless quest and thus an unfalsifiable hypothesis; meanwhile, evolutionary psychology and its sociobiological roots cannot be disproved by either experimental or comparative methods available to science, and thus at most the subject consists of interesting, but untestable and unrefereed postulates that are better regarded as interesting historical thought-experiments. I also liked the author's clear rebuke of relativism or postmodernism's treatment of science, which sought to reduce science to an inferior or equivalent method of earning knowledge about the world as other systems such as magic or religion, through faulty extrapolations of the metaphors of science ('Einstein's theory of relativity means everything goes'; 'scientists' unveiling of nature constitutes rape of Mother Nature') or through false comparisons of their roles in society ('both religion and science are taught early, hence they are both oppressions of people's minds, yet I will still rely on medicine in a way that I don't rely on evangelical healing').
Profile Image for Alan Mills.
546 reviews28 followers
October 22, 2017
Excellent discussion of Global Warming and Creationism, Too much filler

The basic point of this book is that some of what passes as science can be reliably dismissed as pseudoscience, and some is clearly science, but there are gray areas, and it isn't so easy to tell what is "science." However, that does not mean that science isn't a valuable perspective for public policy decision makers.

His core examples are global warming skeptics and the creationism "critique of evolution. He does an excellent job of pulling apart the issues, and identifying the criteria people can use to distinguish truth from agenda driven propoganda.

Surrounding this core are digressions through the history of science from Aristotle to the present, and a discussion of the philosophy of science....which asks what is science actually doing.

Many interesting factoids, and illuminating discussion (e.g., Astrology isn't science at all, as (1) the constellations don't exist; (2) they have shifted an entire month since astrology was founded; and (3) to the extent some "force" is postulated, it would be a force which is not needed to account from any observable phenomena, yet would be far more powerful than gravity, as the stars in question are millions of light years away.

Interestingly, the search for other intelligent life doesn,t fit cleanly in the realm of science.

One final factoid: every single scientific theory in history has been proven wrong....yet they have nonetheless been extraordinarily valuable.

In the end, some of the digressions, while kinda interesting, begin to feel like filler. However, if you are looking for a readable, basic text on the nature of science, this is a good place to start.
Displaying 1 - 30 of 95 reviews

Can't find what you're looking for?

Get help and learn more about the design.